Wygant v. Jackson Board of Education Brief Amicus Curiae
Public Court Documents
June 28, 1985

Cite this item
-
Brief Collection, LDF Court Filings. Wygant v. Jackson Board of Education Brief Amicus Curiae, 1985. fe0c20a3-c99a-ee11-be36-6045bdeb8873. LDF Archives, Thurgood Marshall Institute. https://ldfrecollection.org/archives/archives-search/archives-item/36af6814-aa26-470c-a3ed-bf24435f7ca3/wygant-v-jackson-board-of-education-brief-amicus-curiae. Accessed May 14, 2025.
Copied!
*r IN THE SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES 0CT03ER TERM, 1984 No. 84-1340 WENDY WYGANT, ET A L ., PETITIONERS v . JACKSON 30ARD OF EDUCATION, ET A L . ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT 3RIEF FOR THE UNITED STATES AS AMICUS CURIAE INTEREST OF THE UNITED STATES The government has the responsibility for enforcing numerous statutes prohibiting discrimination on account of race or national origin _/ and, accordingly, has frequently participated in this Court, both as a party and as amicus curiae, in cases presenting constitutional and statutory claims of racial discrimination. / _/ See, e .2 •, 42 U.S.C. 2000h-2; 42 U.S.C. 2000e-5(f) (1); and Executive Order No. 1225Q, 42 U.S.C. 2000d-l note. / E.g., Firef iqhters Local Union No. 1784 v. Stotts, No. 82-206 (June 12, 1934); Fullilove v. Kiutznick, 443 U. (19 80) ; United Steelworkers v . Weber, 443 U .S . 193 (1979); Reqents of the University of California v. Sakke, 438 U.S. S . (1978). 265 5 r - 2 - STATEMENT This case concerns the validity under the Equal Protection Clause of the lay-off provision in the collective bargaining agreement between the board of education and teachers association of Jackson, Michigan. Before the 1972-1973 school year, the Jackson collective bargaining agreement called for lay-offs on a strict seniority basis (Pet. Ad d . 21a). _/ In 1972, however, the board signed a new pact requiring lay-offs on a racial and ethnic basis. Specifically, it agreed that "at no time will there be a greater percentage of minority personnel laid off than the current percentage of minority personnel employed at the time of che layoff" (id. at 3a, 23a). The goal of this system was "to have •at least the same percentage of minority racial representation on each individual staff as is represented by the student population of the Jackson Public Schools" (id. at 13a, 22a, 32a). The agreement defined "minority group personnel" as those "who are Black, American Indian, Oriental, or of Spanish descendancy" (Pet. A d d . la). Petitioners are Jackson teachers who were laid off in * accordance with this provision while "minority" teachers with less seniority were retained. Petitioners brought suit in the United States District Court for the Eastern District of Michigan, claiming that the lay-offs violated the Equal Protection Clause; Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. 2000e et seq.; other federal civil rights statutes (42 U.S.C. 1981, 1983, and 1935); and various state laws. On cross- motions for summary judgment, the court dismissed all of petitioners’ claims. / A d o 11 of the teachers revealed that 96% favored retention of this svstem and oDoosed a freeze offering special protection against: lay-offs to minority group members (Pet. Ad d . 2ia). \ Addressing the teachers' Fourteenth Amendment claim, the court first held that a finding of discrimination was not a Drerecuisite for the racial and ethnic preterences granted by the collective bargaining agreement (Pet. A p p . 25a-27a). Instead, the court held (id. at 28a-31a) that the Equal Protection Clause was satisfied if (1) " ’there is a sound basis for concluding that minority underrepresentation is substantial and chronic, and that the handicap of past discrimination is impeding access [and promotion] of minorities'" and (2) the affirmative action plan meets a test of "reasonableness," _i.e. , is "'substantially related' to the objectives of remedying past discrimination and correcting ’substantial' and 'chronic' underrepresentation" (id. at 28a, 31a), quoting Detroit Police Officers' Association v. Young, 608 F.2d 671, 694, 696 (6th Cir. 1979), cert, denied, 452 U.S. 938 (1981) ) . Apolying this test, the court found "substantial and chronic underrepresentation" solely because the percentage or minority students exceeded the percentage of minority teachers (Pet. App. 29a). The court reasoned (ibid.) that "minority teachers are role-models for minority students." The court then held (id. at 3ia-34a) that the lay-off quota met the test of "reasonableness" (id. at 31a). The court ruled that petitioners' claims under 42 U.S.C. 1981, 1983, and 1985 failed because the lay-off provision was constitutional / (Pet. App. 34a-35a); that petitioners had not satisfied the administrative prerequisites for suit under - 3 - _/ The court also held (Pet. App. 36a) Section 1985(3) was defective for failur that the claim under to allege a conspiracy. r - 4 - Title VII _/ (Pet. Ad d . 34a), and that dismissal of all the federal claims necessitated dismissal of the pendent state claims as well (i_d. at 36a). The court of appeals affi rmed (Pet. App. 2a-19a) in an ODinion that adopted the district court's reasoning and extensively quoted from the district court's opinion (id. at 4a—> 10a). _/ INTRODUCTION AND SUMMARY OF ARGUMENT As amicus curiae in 3rown v. Board of Education, 347 U.S. 483 (1954), the United States argued that the Fourteenth Amendment "established the broad constitutional principle of full and complete equality of all persons under the law, and that it forbade all legal distinctions based on race or color." _/ The schoolchildren and their parents and guardians took the same Dosition, contending that "the Fourteent.n Amendment prohibits a state from making racial distinctions in the exercise of governmental power." / We make the same argument in the present case. / Petitioners were barred from suing under Title VII because they had not filed administrative claims with the Equal Employment Opportunity Commission. 42 U.S.C. 2000e-5(f ) (1) . Petitioners did not appeal the district court's dismissal of their Title VII claims. Moreover, at the time of dismissal, the statute of limitations for filing administrative claims (42 U.S.C. 2000e-5(e)) had already run. Accordingly, petitioners are now relegated to those claims grounded upon the Fourteenth Amendment. _/ Judge Wei ifora concurred, but expressed disagreement with "the majority's view that underrepresentation of minorities could be established by comparing the proportion of minority teachers to minority students rather than to minority representation in the relevant labor market (Pet. App. 15a-19a). He believed, however, that petitioners, as plaintiffs below, bore the burden of proving "the percentage of qualified minority teachers in the relevant labor market (Pet. App. 17a)." / Supp. B r . for the Gov't on Reargument at 115; see also id. at 22, 65 (Equal Protection Clause requires government to be color blind.). _/ Br. for Appellants in Nos. 1, 2, and 4 and Resp. m No. i O on Reargument at 21. r - 5 - In this case, petitioners were laid off from their jobs as school teachers for the sole reason that they are white and the respondent school board, a governmental agency subject to the Fourteenth Amendment, had bound itself in a collective bargaining agreement to an absolute lay-off preference for "employees who are Black, American Indian, Oriental, or of Spanish descendancy (Pet. App. la)." There was no finding by the school board, the courts below, or anyone else, that members of some or all of these groups had been the victims of discrimination by the school board, by the City of Jackson, or by the State of Michigan. There was no inquiry into the reasons for whatever disparities existed between the representation of these groups in the teaching and the student bodies. All there is by way of justification for the racially based misfortune visited upon petitioners are references by the district court and the court of appeals to a history of "societal discrimination" (Pet. App. 4a, 25a), "underrepresentation" of minority teachers (id. at 5a-9a, 28a-31a), and the need to supply "role-models" tor minority students (id. at 8a, 29a-30a). So casual a waving aside of the fundamental Fourteenth Amendment principle of equal treatment for all persons regardless of race and of our republic's basic moral vision of the unity of all mankind cannot be coun-.ena.-ced. First, the courts below drew a wholly unwarranted connection between the general history of racial discrimination in this country, and the statistical underrepresentation of minority group members in the teaching corps relative to the student body- -without even the semblance or an attempt to re.a.e t.-a-. disparity to some pattern or practice of conduct by the school board. Second, there is the further step of using this s u d d o s iticus discrimination to justify a remedy which fu. _..er undoes the connection between wrongdoer and victim to allow a oerson, sav of Asian descent whose ancestors su-._ered 7 - 6 - discrimination in the early history of California, to attain -or that reason a concrete advantage over petitioners in Jackson, Michigan, in 1982. The third and final step in the shambling logic of this enterprise would justify the explicitly racialiy based lay-off of petitioners on the ground that this is necessary to provide "role-models” for minority group students. Stripped or its veneer of unsupoorted psychological and sociological conjecture, this justification can only mean one of two things. it may mean that black, Hispanic or Asian students learn better if they are taught by black, Hispanic or Asian teachers. Or it may mean chat such students, conscious of the injustices done to the groups of which they are members, will draw encouragement and a practical moral lesson from seeing members of their own (or some other) minority grouo in positions of authority anc respect. As to t..e first of these justifications, no evidence for such an empirical effect was ever suggested, let alone examined and subjected .o criticism and refutation. As to the.second, the moral conclusions it teaches beg the question at issue. For one must assume that these students whom it is sought to encourage and morally instruct will be aware of the very system or racial Dreference which delivers role modeis in supposedly sufficient numbers. Hut what is the moral lesson that such a system ly not that ours is a society in which each pe r sen a resu It of his or her own work and talent.. On cn.e mav likelier suppose that su ch a system ( its actual working laid bare) will teach a different and more sinister lesson: that one hundred and twenty years after the end of slavery government may still advance some and suppress others not as individuals but because of the color of their skin. In this brief the United States shall argue, rirst, tr.a. <-h Fourteenth Amendment was intended to assure tne equality before 7 the law of all persons, of whatever race or group; second, that therefore any governmental action based on race or national origin bears the heaviest possible burden of justification; third, that racial quotas cannot lighten much less discharge this burden of justification by claiming to favor blacks or other disadvantaged groups and therefore claiming to be benign; fourth, that comDensating the victims of discrimination is consistent with these principles as the compensation is directed to those who have actually suffered discrimination and that that justification fails when those who have not been wronged are given advantages— at the expense of identified innocent persons— merely because those Dreferred belong to the same racial or ethnic group as others who have suffered from discrimination. Adherence to these constitutional principles is perfectly consistent with a benevolent social policy designed to provide fair opportunity and a sense of real equality to all persons. ARGUMENT THE JACKSON LAY-OFF QUOTA VIOLATES EQUAL PROTECTION I . Equality 3efore the Law Is A Foundational Principle Of American Government The United States' population is the most diverse in the world— indeed, probably in the history of the world. If present trends of immigration and population growth continue, racial and ethnic diversity will significantly increase in the remaining years of this century. This diversity, potentially divisive and enervating, has proved to be a source of strength and cultural richness, a concrete manifestation of the universality or the principles on which this country was founded. Central among those principles is the equality of all persons before the law, regardless or race, religion, or ethnic background. The Declaration or 8 Independence proclaimed that America was different from other countries because: "We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal * * The inscription on the front of this Court reads: "Equal Justice Under Law." This is the principle that as a matter of historical fact has unified the many minorities that make up our population. See N. Glazer, Affirmative Discrimination: Ethnic Inequality and Public Policy 3-32 (1975). This concept finds binding legal expression in the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment: no state shall "deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws." The Equal Protection Clause does not mention any of the characteristics that divide, such as race, religion, or national origin. It sees only "person(s]" and guarantees to every "person" the "equal" protection of the laws. This language means whac it says: the Clause does not permit a state to treat some persons as "more equal" than others. Equality before the law, so magnificent in principle, is often a difficult and uncomfortable concept in practice. There have always been and perhaps will always be voices seeking to carve out soecial exceptions to this principle based on history, orevailing social conditions, temporary need, or expediency. After the era of Reconstruction, such voices prevailed, and the true meaning of the Equal Protection Clause was _ong suDoressed. In 1895, this Court approved the concept of "separate but equal" facilities for blacks and whites and thus upheld the arrest of Homer A. Piessy for occupying a railroad coach reserved for whites. P1essy v. Ferguson, 153 U.S. 537 (1895). According to his petition, Plessy was seven-eighths white and one-eighth black, and "the mixture cr colored blood was net discernible in him" (_ic. st 541). Under Louisiana law, he was black, although in other states he apparently would have been * 9 white (see id. at 552). Whether, if living today, he would be regarded as black or white by the Jackson Board of Education is unclear. What is clear is that his Fourteenth Amendment rights as a person were violated. In one of the most famous and prescient dissents in the history of this Court, the first Justice Harlan wrote (153 U.S. a: 559): (ojur Constitution is color-blind, and neither knows nor tolerates classes among citizens. In respect of civil rights, all citizens are equal before the law. The humblest is the peer of the most powerful. The law regards man as man, and takes no account of his surroundings or of his color when his civil rights as guaranteed by the supreme law or the land are involved. This vision became the creed of the Civil Rights Movement _/ and eventually the nation. _/ It has informed and found expression in numerous decisions of this Court. See, e.g., Loving v . Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967); McLauchlin v . ilorica, 3 7 9 U.S. 184, 191-192 (1964); 3olling v . Sharpe, 347 U.S. 497, 498 (1954). Under those cases, the status of most laws that discriminate on the basis of race or ethnic origin is perfectly clear. They are "constitutionally suspect" and subject to "most rigid scrutiny." McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U.S. at 193. As the Court affirmed only last Term,-"to pass const the 191- t u t i o r. a 1 muster, [a racial classification] must be justified by a compel governmental interest and must be 'necessary . . . to the accomplishment' of its legitimate purpose." Palmo r e v. Sido 1 1 , No. 82-1734 (Apr. 25, 1984), slip op. 4. Furthermore, a suspect classification must be oreciselv "tailored." Dunn v. 3 .urnstern, 40 _/ See page & note , supra. / See, e.g. , Scecial Message to Congress on Civil Rights, 1963 Pub. Paters of President Kennedv 221; Radio and Television Rema rxs UDcn Sicninc the Civil Rights Bill, 1964 Pub. Papers or Lyndon 3. Johnson 842, 343. v - 1 0 - U.S. 330, 343 (1972); Kramer v . Union Free School District, 395 U .S . 621, 627 (1969); Shapiro v . Thompson, 394 U.S. 618 (1969). Beginning with the case of DeFunis v. Odeqaard, 416 U.S. 312 (1974), this Court opened a new chapter in the constitutional history of racial and ethnic discrimination. What purportedly distinguished DeFunis from previous discrimination cases was that the victim, Marco DeFunis, Jr., was not a member of a "minority group, at least as defined by the University of Washington Law School, i.e., he was not "black, Chicano, American Indian, or Filipino (id. at 320)." Thus, discrimination against DeFunis, a Sephardic Jew from a relatively poor background, _/ was claimed to be "benign" and, in the judgment of the University, DeFunis could justly be called upon to sacrirics his aspirations tor a legal career to serve the greater public good. The present case fails into the same pattern. Here, petitioners lest their jobs as teachers because they are not "31ack, American Indian, Oriental, or of Spanish descer.dancy" (Pet. Ad d . la). Those seeking to justify such a departure from one of our most vital and precious constitutional principles must show either (1) that so-called "benign" quotas should not be governed by the same constitutional standards tnat govern other forms of racial and ethnic discrimination or (2) that measures like the Jackson lay-off quota can satisfy those tests. We will address these points in turn. II. Laws That Discriminate In Favor Or Some Minority Groups Must Satisfy The Same Constitutional Standards As Other Forms Of State-Sponsored Racial And Ethnic Discrimination A. This Court has rendered two decisions concerning the constitutionality of racial classifications adoptee by governmental entities for the purpose of ber.efittmg members o~ _/ A . S (1978 ) . ler, 3akke, DeFunis, and Minority Acm sic ns 38-39 II specified minority groups: Regents of the University of California v. 3akke, 438 U.S. 265 (1978); and Fu H i love v. Klutznick, 448 U.S. 448 (1980). While neither case produced a majority opinion, a plurality of the Court appears to nave concluded that state action granting preferences to minorities must satisfy strict scrutiny like all other state-sponsored racial classifications. _/ We fully endorse this conclusion because we see no valid justification for more lenient judicial scrutiny of la*«s uhai. discriminate in favor of some minorities and against a residual category of "whites.” The right to the equal protection of the laws is an "individual," "personal" right. Sheiley v. K .aemer, 334 U.S. 1 , 22 ( 1948 ). See also, e.£., Sweatt v. Painter, 339 U.S. 629 (1950); Laurin v . Oklahoma State Regents, 332 U.S. 631 (1948); Missouri ex rel. Gaines v. Canada, 305 U.S. 337 (j.933). Accordingly, this right applies equally to all persons "without regard to any differences or race, of coior, or or nationality. Yick Wo v. Hook ins, 118 U.S. 356 , 369 ( 1886 ); see also Buchanan v War lev, 245 U.S. 60 , 76 (1917). This right "cannot mean one / This standard of review was stated by justice Powell in Hakke, 438 U.S. a: 290-291. Justice White joined this portionof Justice Powell's opinion (id. at 387 n.7). In Fullilove, Justice Stewart, joined by Justice Rehnquist, declared that racial ana_ ethnic classifications are "inherently suspect and presumptively invalid." 443 U.S. at 521. Justice Powell agreed (id. at 496- 497 n.l), and Justice Stevens declared (id. at 551) that strict scrutiny would apply if a state legislature hac enacted -he Fullilove program. Neither the Chief Justice nor Justice O'Connor has commen on the aDolicable standard of review in this kind or case. i.n Sakke, the Chief Justice joined Justices Stevens, Stewart, ana Rehnauist in an opinion that did not reach the constitutional question, 438 U.S. at 408-421. In Fullilove, his opinion r e u on Congress's unique power to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment 448 U.S. at 472-47*3 , 483 . ted ec Several members of the Court have advocated a somewhat less exacting standard, but they have nevertheless ins-s-ec on a "strict and searching" judicial inquiry (see Bakke, r -q4 3 8 U.S. 3 t 362) ( opinion of Ersnnsn ̂ Whits Ms r s h 3 i 1 / 3 n<3 313 c k mu p. / ̂̂ • ) ' Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 519 (Marshall, J ., concurring judgment). See pages " reascnabler.es 10a, 31a). tes ra. Even this standard is stricter than d i e d bv the courts below (see Pet. Act No. 84-1340 IN THE SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES OCTOBER TERM, 1984 WENDY WYGANT, ET A L ., PETITIONERS v . JACKSON BOARD OF EDUCATION, ET A L . ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT 3RIEF FOR THE UNITED STATES AS AMICUS CURIAE CHARLES FRIED Actino Solicitor General WM. BRADFORD REYNOLDS Assistant Attorney General CHARLES J. COOPER Deputy Assistant Attorney General SAMUEL A. ALITO, JR. Assistant to the Solicitor Genera. WALTER W. BARNETT DAVID K. FLYNN MICHAEL CARVIN Attorneys Department of Justice Washington, D.C. 20530 (202) 533-2217 12 thing when applied to one individual and something else when aDDlied to a person of another color." Bakke, 438 U.S. at 289- 290 (opinion of Powell, J.); see also DeFur.is v. Odeaaard, 416 U.S. at 337 (Douglas, J., dissenting). Equal Protection is a matter of "fundamental principle" and not simply "a matter of whose ox is gored." A Bickel, The Morality or Consent 133 ( 1975) . B. The history of the Fourteenth Amendment dees not support the constitutionality of measures discriminating against "whites." Without doubt, an immediate and pressing purpose of the Amendment was to abolish the legal disabilities imposed on recently freed slaves. See Slaughter-House Cases, 3j J .S . (16 Wall.) 36, 37-71 (1872). But its broader purpose was to proscribe all state-sponsored racial discrimination. The Civil Rights Act of 1866, ch. 31, 14 Stat. 27 et sea., which was enacted by the 39th Congress shortly before it proposes ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment, sheds initial light on the meaning of the Equal Protection Clause in view of the common roots and purposes of these two measures. _/ Congress's unequivocal objective,in passing the 1866 Act was to prohibit official racial discrimination against blacks or whites. Section 1 of the Act guaranteed that "citizens," of every race and color, * * * shall have the same right * * * to full and equal benefit of ail laws and oroceedings for the security or person and Drooertv." Senator Trumbull, the Act's sponsor, declared that its object was to "break down all discrimination between black / The 39th Congress considered the two measures simultar.eo and enacted the Civil Rights Bill approximately two months be proposing ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment. One of t ourooses of the Fourteenth Amendment was "to incorporprimary p the guarar u s - y £ c 0 he ate .ie s o: the Civil Rights Act of 1866 in the organic is'- of the land" and thus insulate them from repeal or invalicati: Hurd v. Hodge, 334 U.S. 24, 32-33 (1948); see also, e.c., Jor.e s v . Alfred H. Maver C o ., 392 U.S. 409, 436 (1958). In addition, Section 1 of the .Act was a model for tne Equal Protection Clause. Frank & Munro, The Original Understanding "Ecual Protection of the Laws 50 Col. Rev. 13! 140 (1950 ) . 13 men and white men" and that it applied "to white men as well as black men." Cong. Globe, 39th Cone., 1st Sess. 599 (1866). As Senator Howard, later a framer of the Fourteenth Amendment, commented, "[i ]n respect to all civil rights, there is to be hereafter no distinction between the white race and the black race . " Id . at 504 . The purpose and effect of the Equal Protection Clause were the same. As proposed in the Reconstruction Committee, _/ Section 1 of the Fourteenth Amendment provided: No discrimination shall be made by any state, nor by the United States, as to civil rights of persons because of race, color, or previous condition of servitude. [ /] / Before Section 1 of the Fourteenth Amendment was cast m present form, the 39th Congress considered several proposed Amendments that spoke directly to the ecua before the law Committee on Reconstruc* its ty of the races One of the alternatives recommended to the - '.on by Senator Fessenden stated that provisions in the Constitution or laws of any State, wnereby a± r civil rights or privileges, r, shall be inoperative and he Joint Committee of Fifteen all i distinction is mace in political o on account of race, creed or cole void." Kendrick, The Journal of t on Reconstruction 50 (1914). Late amendment provicing: because of race, color in civil rights or Globe, 39th Cong., Senator Stewart offeree an All discriminations among the people or previous condition of servitude, eith« the right of suffrage are prohibited." Cong 1st Sess. 1906 (1866). Kendrick, suora, 83-34. 4 Although the committee changed this language, it is apparent that it did not intend to alter the principle of racial equality before the law. _/ This was confirmed in the opening speech by the House floor leader, Representative Stevens. Section 1, he explained, guaranteed individuals of both races exactly the same treatment by the states (Cong. Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess. 2459): Whatever law punishes a white man for crime shall punish the black man precisely in the same way and to the same degree. Whatever law protects the white man shall afford "equal" protection to the black man. Whatever means of redress is afforded to one shall be afforded to all. Later,-he added (id. "abolishes all class at 2766) that the Equal Protection Clause of legislation in the States" and "protects the black man in his fundamental rights with the same shield which it throws over the white man." leader, Senator Howard, provided the In the Senate, the floe same unequivocal explana ion (Cong. Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess. 2765 (1356)). The deliberations on the Fourteenth Amendment also show that Congress specifically intended to protect two groups of whites add/ Representative Bingham first sought unsuccessfully this provision the present language of the Equal Protection Clause (Kendrick, sutra, at 85), and Section 1 was adopted as it stood (by a vote of 10 to 2) (Kendrick, supra, at 86-37) . Bingham later succeeded in adding as a new Section 5 all of wha is new the second sentence of Section 1 (again by a vote of 10 2) (Kendrick, supra, at 37), but (Kendrick, suora, at 98-99). Finally, he this was later deleted convinced to substitute this Section 5 for what was then Sect time the vote was 10 to 3) (Kendrick, supra, history--with the committee voting at .06). various times r 0 ccmmi ttee on 1. (This . This to adept the and together— strongly suggests that the express meaning of the original version— banning all "discrimination" by government "because of race [or] color" was regarded as incorporated wi the version finally reported. For accounts of the committee proceecincs, see History of the Supreme Court or tne Lnited States ( vo 1. 6, o t . 1 — Re-const ruct ion thin and Reunio DV at 1270-1274, 1231-1283 (19 71)); J . J ames, __ Fourteenth Amendment 103-115 (1956); H. Flack 65-59 (1965); H. i Amendment 71-74 :d the Secrecation C . Fair ma n The Framinq of the The Ad< ition :ine Fourteenth Amendment Mear.ina of : h e F o i . 0 0 n t Oricinal Understanomc Rev. 1 , 40-45 ( 1955 ) . Meyer , (1977 ) ;' Dec i s i: r. e History and 3ickei, Tne m 59 Harv. L.O 3 rt r r . 3 “ who were in real danger of deprivation of civil rights. First, the term "Derson," rather than "citizen," was used in the Equai Protection Clause to encompass aliens. Although the earliest draft of Section 1 of the Fourteenth Amendment, introduced in December 1865 by Representative Stevens, applied only to "citizen[sj" (Cong. Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess. 14 (1865)), by February 1866 the Reconstruction Committee had approved a different version, offered by Representative Bingham, that guaranteed equal protection to all "person!s i." _/ Defending this amendment on the House floor, Bingham asked on February 28 (Cong. Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess. 1090 (1866)): "Is it not essential to the unity of the Government and the people that all persons, whether citizens or strangers, within this land, shall have ecual Drotection m every State in this Union in the rights of life and liberty and property?" Nine days later, commenting on the use of the term "citizen" in Section 1 of tne Civil Rights Act, he stated (39th Cong., 1st Sess. 1292 (1366)): The alien is nor a citizen. You propose to enact this law, you say, in the interests of the freedmen. But do you propose to allow these discriminations to be made in States against the alien and stranger? Can such legislation be sustained by reason or conscience? * * * * Is it not as unjust as the unjust State legislation you seek to remedy? C_/1 _/ Kendrick, supra, 62. / Earlier, Representative Stevens, the floor manager of the Fourteenth Amendment, and Reoresentative Conkling, another member of the Reconstruction Committee, had made the same point. Cong. Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess. 359 (1866) (remarks of Rep. Conkling); id. at 537 (remarks or Rep. Stevens). \ \ \ - 16 - In 1866, the overwhelming majority of aliens were white, _/ since the first sentence of Section 1 of the rourteenth Amendment had confirmed that virtually all freed siaves were citizens. _/ The other group of whites that Congress specifically wanted to protect were white Unionists in the South. When asked if the Amendment's sole purpose was to protect black freedmen, Bingham responded (Cong. Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess. 1088 (1866) that it was intended "as well to protect the thousands and tens of thousands and hundreds of thousands of loyal white citizens o. the United States whose property, by State legislation, r.as beer, rested from them under confiscation, and protect them a-so from banishment." See also id. at 1090-1091. Those who argue that the history of the Reconstruction era supports the constitutionality of prererences for blacks rely chiefly on laws relating to the Freedmen's Bureau. _/ But whatever light these statutes shed on the intended meaning of the Equal Protection Clause, they do not support current measures containing racial and ethnic preferences. Rather, they are examples of compensation for actual, identified victims o_ d i sc r imi na t ion . See Cong. Glebe, 39th Cong., j.st Sess. 9-,0 (1886) (remarks of Sen. Trumbull). They provided assistance, not to blacks generally, but to "freedmen," individuals who were the victims of slavery. _/ Moreover, these laws aiso provided substantial assistance for white refugees; in fact, figures / See 1 Bureau of the Census, United States 99, 106, 108 (1975 Histor :al St ;istic s ol / That prevision states that ail persons born or r.aturc-izec in the United States and subject to its jurisdiction are citizens. This aoolied to virtually ail former sisvsa, s_nce imDO rtation of slaves ended i n 1808 (Art. I , § 9, Co., i). / See 3 r . of NA_AC? legal Defense and Education Fund, Inc. as Amicus Curiae in Bakke, Mo. 76-811, at 10-53. / Supporters emphasized that newly freec s.aves nac special^ needs resulting directly from years of bondage. See Cong. G_obe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess. 939 (1866) (remarks of Sen Trumbull); id. at 630 (remarks of Rep. Hubbard). provided to Congress showed that two-thirds as many whites as blacks had received rations f rom the 3ureau. Cong. Globe, 39th Cong. , 1st Sess. 940 (1866 ) ,. _/ It is thus difficult to discern in these laws any support for the constitutionality of current measures granting preferences, regardless of individual circumstances, to any black person or, even more remotely, to any member of other minority groups. _/ C. Permissive judicial scrutiny of "benign" discrimination is sometimes defended on the principle that the courts have a SDecial duty to protect minorities lacking political power. In the words of Dean John Hart Ely, a leading proponent of this view: / The initial act (Act of Mar. 3, 1865, ch. 90, 13 Stat. 507 Tl865 )) established for one year a "bureau of refugees, freedmen, and abandoned lands" (sec. 1), authorized the Secretary of War to provide aid to "destitute and suffering refugees and freedmen and their wives and children" (sec. 2), and permitted abandoned and confiscated lands in the Conrederate stares to be set aside for the use of "loyal refugees and freedmen" (sec. 4). The second act (Act of July 16, 1366, ch. 200, 14 Stat. 173 et sec. extended the life of the bureau for two years (§ 1), continued aid to needy refugees and freedmen (§ 2, 5, 14 Stat. 114), addressed various administrative matters (§ 3, 4, 14 Stat. 174), confirmed tax sales of certain lands to blacks (§ 6, 14 Stat. 174), orovided for the disposition and administration or other confiscated and abandoned land (§ 7-10, 11, 14 Stat. 175- 176), allowed freedmen to continue occupying certain land under an Army field order until after the harvest and receipt by them of compensation for any improvements (§ 12, 14 Stat. 1/6), and instructed the commissioner to cooperate with benevolent societies for the aid of treedmen (§ 13, 14 Stat. 176). Finally, section 14 of the Act (14 Stat. 176), far from granting a racial Dreferer.ee, guaranteed tine rights and immunities or all citizens" in the Confederate states "without respect to race or color, or Drevious condition of slavery," and authorizec n i n t a r y tribunals to enforce these rights. In 1868, the Bureau was continued for an additional year (Act of July 6, 1868, ch. 135, 15 Star. 33). in sum, the Freedmen's 3ureau measures provide no examples or race-conscious relief for non-victims. / Three other minor Reconstruction-era statutes have oee.n cited as examoles of race-conscious relief. One was a S j-5,000 appropriation*"for the relief of freedmen or destitute colored people in the District of Columbia" (Res. of Mar. 15, 1367, ^14 Stat. 20). The others established special protective procedures to ensure that black servicemen in former slave states were not cheated of their pay by claims agents. It seems sate to assu...e that virtually everyone aided by these enactments was a direct victim of slavery or racial oppression. 18 When the group that controls the decision making process classifies so as to advantage a minority and disadvantage itself, the reasons for being unusually suspicious, and, consequently, employing a stringent brand of review, are lacking I A White majority is unlikely to disadvantage icself for reasons of racial prejudice * * *. Ely, The Constitutionality of Reverse Racial Discrimination, 41 U. Chi. L. Rev. 723, 735 (1974); see also J. Ely, Democracy and Distrust 170-172 (1980). This argument has at least three major defects . First, it greatly oversimplifies and distorts the meaning of the Ecual Protection Clause, making it nothing more than an enforcement mechanism for one particular theory of democratic government. There is no evidence that those who framed, proposed, and ratified the Fourteenth Amendment had this theory in mind. Instead, they believed for a variety of reasons including the fact that immutable characteristics such as race and ethnicity are almos never relevant to a legitimate legislative purpcse--that racial and ethnic classifications "are by their very nature odious to a free people whose institutions are founded upon the doctrine of eaualitv." Hirabavashi v. United States, 320 U.S. 81, 100 ( 1942 ) . Second, Ely's argument is an oversimplification because it unqualifiedly equates numerical majority with political power and assumes that minority groups are politically powerless. In reality, the distribution of political power in a democracy is considerably more complex. Governmental decisionmakers directly or indirectly answerable to the voters are not always responsive to the majority's wishes. In addition, interest groups representing small segments or the population are sometimes aoie Preference in Law (Continued) favorable to the g r electoral majority. of "Benic n" Racial i Col. L . Rev. 557, \ \ Third, this theory assumes the existence of a polity with a monolithic white majority and black minority. The United States, however, is a nation of many minorities _/ (many of which . overlao) and many, many political jurisdictions--50 spates and nearly 80,000 units of local government. _/ Racial and ethnic groups are unevenly distributed among these jurisdictions, causing the terms "majority" and "minority" to have varying meanings. In more than 75 counties, blacks exceed 50% of the population; in 37 counties, more than 50% of the population is Hispanic. In eight of the ten largest cities, blacks and Hispanics constitute a majority. _/ Asian-Americans substantially outnumber whites in Hawaii. _/ in many communities, individuals of other cohesive, traditionally disfavored grouDS constitute substantial voting Dices. Because of these factors, different groups, whether alone or in coalition, are in the majority in different jurisdictions. if the standard for constitutional scrutiny were to depend upon whether a preference benefited a "minority" or the electoral majority, the meaning of equal protection would have to vary from oiace to d a c e and time to time and wou-d thus acquire an "accordion-like quality." Per unis, 416 U.S. at 343 (Douglas, J., dissenting). The courts would also be compelled to make a sensitive and sophisticated assessment of the real distribution of political power in each community. This is an inquiry for which courts are ili-suitec. These problems can be illustrated - 19 - (1975). / See United Jewish Organizations v. Carey, 430 U.S. 144, i85 11977) (3urger, C.J., dissenting) ("the 'whites' category consists of veritable galaxy of national origins, ethnic backgrounds, and religious denominations. It simp_v cannot oe assumed that the * * * interests or all whites are even substantially identical"). / Bureau of the Census, County and City Data Book 1983 (-933) / Statistical Abstract at 25-25. Statistical Abstract 11 20 by attempting to apply this same theory to cender classifications. Should measures disadvantaging women be leniently reviewed because female voters outnumber male voters? Should measures disadvantaging men be leniently scrutinized because men occupy most electoral posts? This Court has not drawn such distinctions but instead applies precisely the same level of judicial review no matter which gender is disadvantaged. See, e . a Mississippi University for Women v . Hogan, 458 U.S. 718, 723 S> n.9 (1982). D. Permissive judicial scrutiny of racial preferences for blacks and members of some other minority groups is sometimes defended on the ground that such measures compensate for past wronas or for what is termed "societal" discrimination. We disagree with this approach because it assumes compensation and relaxes scrutiny before accurately assessing whether a measure is truly compensatory. In our view, nothing less than strict scrutiny can be trusted to determine whether a measure is truly compensatory. The problems inherent in any aoorcacn less exacting than strict scrutiny are illustrated by the intermediate scrutiny test advocated bv several members of this Court as the apropriate standard for reviewing purportedly compensatory preferences. _/ Applying this test, proponents have approved preferential benefits for inaividuals not shown to have suffered from any past _/ See Fullilove, 443 U.S. at 517-521 (Marshall, J., concurring) Bakke, 438 U.S. at 324-379 (opinion of Brennan, White, Marshall, and Blackmun, JJ). Under this test, a racia ethnic classification "designed to further remedial purposes" must "serve important governmental objectives" and must be "substantially* related to the achievement of those objectives Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 519 (Marshall, J., concurring) . _ In addition, there must be some rational oasis tor concluding th the preferred groups are mere deserving of compensation than groups disfavored. (3akke, 4 3 8 U.S. at 359 n .35 (opinion or Brennan, White, Marshall, and Blackmun, J J . )). or it 21 \ discrimination; / preferential medical school admissions for members of minority groups that were already over represented in the student body; / and preferential treatment for minority businessmen whose economic resources and opportunities clearly exceeded those of the average citizen. _/ Indeed, this test has been found to allow both discrimination in favor of and discrimination against the very same minority groups and ail in the name of compensation. _/ This dramatically illustrates the need for strict scrutiny to identify those measures that are truly remedial and compensatory. / Bakke, 438 U.S. at 377-378 (opinion of Brennan, White,^ Marshall, and Blackmun, JJ.); Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 517-522 (Marshall, J., concurring). / This was true of Chinese— and Japanese—American students in Bakke. See Posner, The Bakke Case and the Future of "Affirmative Action," 57 Cal. L. Rev. 171, 185-186 (1979). / Compare Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 520-521 (Marshall,_J., concurring), with id. at 538-539 (Stevens, J., dissenting). / The stature in Fullilove, which some juscicsa would h g v e tested and sustained under intermediate scrutiny (443 U.S. a^^ 517-522) (Marshall, J., concurring)), gave a preference to all Spanish-SDeaking citizens (see id. at 459). By contrast, the admission's program in Bakke, which likewise passed intermediate scrutiny (438 U.S. at 355-379) (opinion of Brennan, White, Marshall, and Blackmun, J J . )), favored only "Chicanos," l .e. , Mexican-Amer icans , while all other Hispamcs, including such grouos as Puerto Ricans, Cubans, and Central Americans, were reauired to shoulder part of the burden or providing compensation (see id. at 274).. Such absurd results are not a quirk of the particular >.esw employed but are an inevitable consequence or attempting to orovide compensation to groups rather than individual^ victims. Many grouos have suffered substantial discrimination in this^ country. Putting aside the special case of past discrimination against blacks, it is very dirficult to say with any assurance that any of the remaining groups suffered greater discrimination than the rest. A "rational" case can be made that each group is especially deserving; but it is doubtful that a substantially stronger argument can be made on behalf or any group. Accordingly, if there must simply be a rational basis for choice of groups preferred in an affirmative action plan. Government is aooarently free to pick and choose a.iicr.'M minority groups as it wishes. (The intermediate scrutiny test advocated by members of this Court, contrary to its name, requires only a basis for the choice ofV' m - the the rational basis for the choice or groups to be preferred (see note , supra)), and thus has predictably been found to permit compensatory discrimination in raver or and against the same groups). If anything more than a rational basis must oe it seems doubtful that any of the croups noted above can oreferrec. sne be 22 E. A final argument for permissive scrutiny of measures discriminating in favor of certain minority groups would justify them in terms of their supposedly benign symbolism: such classifications do not stigmatize or brand the victims as inferior. _/ This argument is wrong'as well. It loses sight of the equal protection ideal that each individual should be free to achieve his or her place in society without being disabled by government on the basis of race or ethnic background. Instead of focusing on the simple command of the Equal Protection Clause, this theory suggests that the Clause is more concerned with tne symbolism than with the concrete effects of racial and ethnic discrimination. But surely the immediate effects of discrimination — loss of money, a job, education, a place to live, etc.— are no less important than any accompanying symbolism. This argument fails as well even on its own terms. A defense of racial preferences concretely disadvantaging and benefiting persons who are neither the proven beneficiaries nor victims of discrimination on "symbolic" groucs is perilously vague and subjective. See Bak k e , 433 U.S. at 294-295 n . 3 4 (opinion of Powell, J). The symbolism of benign concern intended bv the defenders of such schemes may not■be the symbolism discerned by the schemes' beneficiares and victims or the public at large. These may rather infer that in our society benefits and opportunities are not to be obtained by merit but by successful manipulation of the politics or racial and group patronage. Nor dees it seem possible to identify any significant Generic differences between the potential symoolic erfects of disabilities and preferences. A disability may be seen as a brand of inferiority, but a paternalistic preference may carry exactly the same symbolic meaning as many members of this Court / See Fullilove v . Klutz nick, 443 U.S. 518 (Marshall, J., concurring). 23 have noted. _/ A disability may single out a minority group and thereby endorse and even encourage public hostility towards its members. 3ut, again, so may a preference; a preference may arouse sharo resentment among those who are not preferred. F. In arguing for a unitary standard of review for all racial and ethnic classifications, we do not equate or confuse a measure like the Jackson lay-otf quota with the vicious discrimination of the Jim Crow era; neither the motivation nor the macnitude of the societal harm is comparable. However, the Equal Protection Clause is not merely a protection against the most flagrant wrongs. It embodies a broad principle of equality that is subverted unless applied equally to all racial and ethnic classifications. A. Bickel, The Morality of Consent 132-133 (1975 ) . Laws Granting preferences to members of enumerated minority grcuos are also far from benign in practical effect. Such preferences inevitably harm innocent individuals. Whether a Plessv is ejected from a railroad coach because he is one—eighth black or laid-off because he is seven-eighths white, the concrete wrong to him is much the same. Whether a DeFunis is excluded from law school because he is Jewish or because he is not "3lack, American Indian, Oriental, or of Spanish cescendancy, his personal aspirations are equally thwarted. Preferences also perpetuate and fester racial and ethnic divisions. And in a pluralistic and democratic society such as ours, when preferen ces are gran ted to some groups, there is inevitable pressure for similar preferences to benefit every arouD that can incur.t a claim of past discrimination. Racial and ethnic preferences necessarily mar the law with definitions of racial and ethnic types, laws that are ciscuieting 1 v reminiscent or abhorrent measures enactec m otr.e See Posner, suor 20 . 2 times and places. / And if preferences are sustained, a ready made legal framework is thereby created for racial and ethnic policies of more malevolent design. III. The Jackson Lay-Off Quota Cannot Satisfy The Constitutional Standards Applicable To Measures Containing Racial And Ethnic Classifications The lay-off quota adopted by the Jackson school board emphatically flunks the constitutional standards governing racial classifications. A. The lower courts justified the Jackson measure in large part on the theory that it serves to provide "role models" for minority youths, but this superficially appealing justification is multiply flawed. In the first place, we believe that special wariness is aDpropriate whenever an attempt is made to justify a racial classification, not for the purpose or rig.nting past wrongs, but simply because it is asserted that social institutions would work better or more smoothly. Variations or this arcument prevailed in ?1essy and Hirabavasri, with regrettable results. .However, except for such wrong turns, the Court has consistently and soundly rejected calls that the equal- protection rights of individuals be sacrificed to serve some abstract societal good. See, e.c., ?aImore v. Sidoti , No. 82- 17 3 4 (Apr. 25, 1984); Lee v . Washington, 390 'J. S . 333 (1963); Cooser v. Aaron, 353 U.S. 1, 16 (1958); "[t]he Equal Protection Clause commands thi elimination of racial barriers, not their creaticrn i p o rder to satisfy our theory of how society See Fullilove, 443 U.S. at 534 n.5 (Stevens dissenting 25 should be organized." DeFunis v. Odegaard, 416 U.S. at 342 (Douglas, J., dissenting). _/ In this case, the role-model justification adopted by the lower courts falls far short of sustaining the jackson l^y of- quota. We do not dispute the fact that young people benefit from Dositive role models. Nor do we dispute the fact that minority youths, disheartened by past and present discrimination, often need minority role—models. 3ut it is most doubtful that -he Jackson lay-off cuota will serve or is needed to serve this goa-. The Jackson measure, like all racial preferences, may undermine, rather than foster, minority role models. _/ See Full!love v. Klutznick, 448 U.S. at 545, 547 (Stevens, J., dissenting); United Jewish Organizations v. Carey, 430 U.S. 144, 173-174 (1977) (Brennan, J., concurring in part); Regents of the University o f California v . Bakke, 438 U.S. at 2 9 o (opinion of / The role model justification seem clearly inconsistent with Palmore, which held that a state court, m awarding custody of a child, could not rely upon the race of the divorced mother's new husband. Few would deny that a child's most important role models are usually his parents. Thus, if a state's interest in providing children with role models of the same race were sufficient to override the principle or racial equality contained in the Fourteenth Amendment, it would appear that a state court should at least be permitted to into account in awarding custody. ___ prohibited this practice. The invalidity of the role-model justification in the present, weaker context would appear to follow a fortiori. take the race of the new husband But Palmore properly / As Professor Thomas Sowell has written (Black Fcucaticn, Myths and Tragedies 29 2 (197 2) (empbasis m original)): What all the arguments and campaigns for quotas are really saying, loud and clear, is that black people just don't have it, and that they will have to be giver. something in order to have something. The devastating impact of this message on black people--particularly black young people--will outweigh any few extra jobs that may result from this strategy. Those black pecole who are already competent, and who could be instrumental in producing more competence among the rising generation, will be completely undermined, as c-ack becomes synonymous — in the minds or black and white alike--with incompetence, and black achievement becomes synonymous with cnarity or payoffs. 25 Powell, J.); 448 U.S. at 531 (Stewart, J., dissenting); DeFunis v. Odecaard, 416 U.S. at 343 (Douglas, J., dissenting); Posner, The DeFunis Case and the Constitutionality of Preferential . Treatment of Racial Minorities, 1974 Sup. Ct. Rev. 1, 17 & n.35. The most powerful role models are those who have succeeded without a hint of favoritism. Henry Aaron would not be regarded as the all-time home run king, and he would not be a model for vouth, if the fences had been moved in whenever he came to the plate. There are ether, better ways for the schools to provide role models for minority youth. Any discrimination against minority teaching applicants can and should be stamped out. Minority group members who have achieved success in various walks of life can be invited and encouraged to visit the schools and to discuss their careers and the students' aspirations. Courses of study can be developed so as not to overlook the notable contributions of minorities. The schools can and should ensure that teachers, of whatever race, are sensitive to the special needs of minority students. In view of these alternatives, the Jackson lay-off quota is net necessary to provide minority role models, and it accordingly cannot be justified on this ground. Palmore, slip cp. 4; Bakke, 438 U.S. at 314-315 (opinion of Powell, J.). At the very least, the beard has failed to carry its burden of showing a compelling educational neec for its particular program, which (a) treats all "minority" and nonminority teachers as fungible for role model purposes _/, (b) aims for statistical paritv between the percentage of minority students ana teachers and (c ) in the meantime, prohibits any lay-off that would _/ It is far from obvious that a teacher be the preferred minority groups is necessarily serving as a role model for students belongin preferred group than is a teacher belonging t group. Fcr example, is it clear that black s inspired .by a teacher of Chinese or Japanese teacher of Jewish or Lebanese heritage? longing to one of any more capable of g to another o a disfavored tudents will be more ar.cestrv than by a 27 decrease whatever percentage of minority teachers happens to have been achieved at the time when lay offs become necessa.y. The roie-mocel justification also beckons down forbidden paths. It is an argument for quotas in every profession and occupation, for minority students properly aspire to careers in every walk of life. Indeed, the logic of the role-model argument might serve to justify segregated classrooms. If the educational development of minority students urgently demands the presence in their schools of minority teachers to serve as role models indeed demands the presence of minority teachers in mathematical proportion to the racial composition of the student body then it is not easy to see why minority students would not be served best if they were actually taught by minority teachers. These dangerous implications are underlined by the fact that the role-mocel argument or variants of it have frequently been advanced as a defense bv school boards charged with illegally segregating minority teachers in predominantly minority schcois. _/ -'Or example, in Smith v . Board of education, 365 : . 2d 770 (3th Cir . 1966), the school board argued that it could legally prerer white teachers to instruct white pupils because "rapport between teacher and oupii * * * may be unattainable wr.ere they a^e of different races and this diff erer.ce a£ £ects attitudes, personal philosophies and prejudices." Id. at 781. The court, m an opinion by then Judge Elackmun, rejected this argument in unequivocal terms (id. at 782). 3 . The lower courts also justified the Jackson measure as a cure for "subs tantial and chronic underrepresentat / See, e .a ., Reed v. Rhodes, 607 F . 2d 714 (6 th cert . denied, 445 U.S. 935 (1980); United States v D 1st rict, 521 F . 2d 530 (8th Cir.), cert, denied, 4 ( 19 7 5) ; Morcan v. Kerrigan, 509 F.2d 580 (1st Cir. 1974 ), cer.. denied, 421 U.S. 963 (1975); 01 iver v . Micnican Sta^e Bos.c Zcucat ion, 508 F .2d 173 (6th Cir. 1974), cert, denied, 421_U,.S. 963 (1975); Arthur v . Nyquist, 415 F . Supp. 904 (W.D.N.T. 1976), aff'c in part and rev'a in part, 573 F.2c i34 (2c Cir.), cert, denied, 439 U.S. 860 (1378). 2 3 minority teachers. But the use of racial classifications for the sole purpose of curing statistical underrepresentation (or, in Dlainer terms, imposing quotas) is proscribed by the Fourteenth Amendment. As Justice Powell concluded in Bakke (438 U.S. at 307): "Preferring members of any one group for no reason other than race or ethnic origin is discrimination for its own sake. This the Constitution forbids." _/ C. 1. Finally, the lower courts justified the Jackson measure as a means to redress "societal discrimination." We readily agree that providing a remedy for individual victims of discrimination is a compelling interest, but measures granting preferences' to ail members of a few minority groups cannot be justified in the name of compensation of "societal discrimination." In the first place, such measures are compensatory or remedial in name only. Because the Equal Protection Clause orctects oersonal not group rights, a measure cannot oe fairly characterized as a remedy for a violation of equal protection unless it provides relief to an individual who was personally victimized by discrimination. Nor can a measure oe termed remedial if the benefit conferred is not m some way measured by the nature and extent of the prior violation. When benefits do not corresoond to any identified prior wrong and are not directed / In relying upon what they viewed as chronic underrepre sentation of minority teachers to justify the Jackson lay-ofr cucta, the lower courts were apparently confused by Jr. i tec Steelworkers v. Weber, 443 U.S. 193 (1979), m which tr.e Court Riants Act of 1964 was notneia mac ’itle VII of the Civ: violated bv a orovisior. in a private-sector collective bargaining granting racial preferences in a craft-training Weber, by its own terms, however, has no application in ag reei.e prcgra involve state action ana thus ed violation of the Equal Protection Moreover, even if applicable, Weber would s' decisions in this case because the he oercer.tage of minority teachers m the work force exceeded the percer.tace on the Jackson faculty (compare Weber , 44 3 U.S. at 193-199). In addition, m t m s case, 1 acial preference caused the discharge of .tv emolevees the present case because did "not or 0 5 0 r. u an alleg Clause" (id . a Z 200). Mo not support the lower cou record cces ’■nr show that un11xe *eo i nnocen t r. in-mino: comoare id. at 203). to the victim of such a wrong, they cannot in any meaningful sense be termed compensatory or remedial. For essentially the same reasons, categorical preferences can never be regarded as precisely tailored to remedy discrimination. Such measures are fatally under inclusive because the grouDS usually singled out for preferential treatment are not the only groups that have been discriminated against in this country." Posner, The Bakke Case and the Future of "Affirmative Action," 67 Cal. L. Rev. 171, 176 (1979). See also J. Fishkm, Justice, Equal Opportunity and the Family 9S-99 (1983); J. Wilkinson, From Brown to 3akke 278-279 (1979). Categorical preferences are also impermissibly over inclusive because "[i]n today's society, it constitutes far too gross an over simplification to assume that every Negro, Spanish-speaking citizen, Oriental, [or] Indian * * * suffers from the effects of oast or present racial discrimination." Fullilove, 443 U.S. at 530 n.12 (Stewart, J., dissenting); see also id. at 537-538, 546 (Stevens, J., dissenting). Indeed, it is one of the ironies of racial oreferer.ces that these who benefit are se_dcm the mest disadvantaged. Many minority group members and some minority grouDS as a whole have now surpassed the residual category c_ "whites" in income, education, and ether measures of success. _/ Furthermore, many individuals given preference under affirmative action plans, while perhaps disadvantaged in some respects, are not even the indirect victims of discrimination in this country. This is often true of recent immigrants who happen to fail into one of the preferred groups. Precise tailorino r ecu ires that the remedy fit a proven violation of law. See, e.o., Davtcna Board of education v . - 29 - _/ This is true, for Americans, groups that are included among the lay-off cuota. See T. 49 , 187 (*1983). examoie, of Chinese- and Japanese- suffered severe de jure discriminat minorities given preference in the Sowell, The economics and Politics :<s: 30 Brinkman, 433 U.S. 406, 420 (1977); Milliken v . 3radlev, 41S U . S . 717, 738, 746 (1974). (An equal protection remedy is "necessarily designed * * * to restore the victims or discriminatory conduct to the position they would have occupied in the absence of such conduct"). This means, as Justice Stewart stated in Fullilove (448 U.S. at 530 n.12), that ”[e]xcept to make whole the identified victims of racial discrimination, the guarantee of equal protection prohibits the government from taking detrimental action against innocent people on the basis of the sins of others of their own race." Justice Stevens recognized the same principle in Fulli] at 541) that the statutory preference ' ■e whe n he observed (id .nnot be justified as a been "wrongfully acts . /excluded from the market for public contracts." _/ No other remedial principle is compatible with the cardinal rule that Government may neither favor nor disadvantage a person solelv because of race or ethnicity. When government provides comoer.sation to individual victims, government is not itse_r making or implementing a racial classification. The ciass of / In Fullilove, neither the piura., e :he Co ;et- .ity opinion nor tha justice Powell approved the award of benefits to ncn-vic the exoer.se of innocent third parties. In the plurality the Chief Justice stressed (443 U.S. at 436) that considering only a facial challenge to the minority orovision and that equal protection claims arising out o specific awards that "cannot be justified * * * as a rem present effects of identified prior discrimination * * * await future cases." The Chief Justice also emphasized that a preference should be given tCcnaress's mtentic loose firms "whose comoetitive oositu imoairerpr! t ims cpi urt a s i a *- edy 1 mu s i o on' he nion, was e effects of disadvantage and discrimination" (id. at 471; see also id. at 464) and that the administrative process would prevent misaopiications of Congress's goals (id. at 437-489). Tne Fullilove plurality did not suggest that the statute at issue in that case, which may have ”pres[sed] the outer limits cf cong r es s icr.a 1 authority" ( id. at 490), would have been upheld had it extended ©references to firms based solely on race rather tnan their "impaired * * * competitive position" resulting from the "□resent effects of past discrimination" in government construction contracts. None cf these factors is present here. Petitioners were personally and substantially harmed oy the lay-off ouota, and no effort whatsoever was made to inquire whether these ©referred at petitioners' expense were the actual victims cf discrimination or disadvantage. 31 victims compensated may all be members of the same racial or ethnic group, but this is merely because the guilty party's unlawful behavior was defined by race. Nor does any other remedial principle pay sufficient heed to the rights of innocent parties. Although a valid remedy for individual discrimination may require some sharing of the burden bv innocent parties Fullilove, 448 U.S. at 484 (plurality), (Franks v . Bowman Transportation C o ., 424 U.S. 747, 777 (i976); Albemarle PaDer Co. v. Moody, 422 U.S. 405 (1975) ) , such individuals will simply be placed in the situation that would have existed had the discrimination not occurred. 3ut un.ess a remedy benefits an actual victim of discrimination, the government has [no] greater interest m helping one individua- than in refraining f corn harming another" ( 3 a k k e , 438 U.S. a u 309 (opinion of Powell, J)). _/ 2. The Jackson measure cannot be justified as a means or orovidi.oa comoensstion for individual victims or discrimination. Neither the school board nor the courts bsicw found that the beard had ever engaged in discrimination. The absence cl such a finding alone requires the invalidation of the lay-off quota. Bakke, 438 U.S. at 302-310 (opinion of Powell, J.); see a*so Bushev v. New York State Civil Service Ccmmiss ion, No. 8^-3 36 / The same remedial principle guiced the Court in its rscer.i. decision regarding the scope of a federal court's remedial authority under Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 196-,, ^2 U.S.C. 2000e et sec. See Firefighters Local Union No. 1784 v. Stotts, No. 82-206 (June 12, 1984). With much the same values and interests at stake, the Court ruled that the pc.icy bemr.d the remedial orovision of Title VII, Section 706(g), 42 U.S.C. 2000e-5(g), is to "provide make-whole relief only to tnose who have been actual victims of discrimination." Stotts, s±ip^op. 16-17; see also Teams t e r s v . United States, 431 U.S. 324, 367-371 (1977). This holding is particularly instructive since Title VIi hes been held to allow greater leeway for racial preferences than would be permittee for an entity subject to tr.e Fou r •_ ee n t h ̂ Ajti encment. See United Steel'workers v • Weber r suers . j us t ics O ’Conner implicitly pointed out the when she wrote in Stotts (concurrina slio o c . at 5 (emonasis precedent, that "[a] court may u to prevent future violations and of unlawful discrimination." the breacth ■ L. slip op no Fourteent s 0 its remed to comoensa • — -k k k 32 (Jan. 8, 1985) (opinion of Rehnquist, J . , 3urger , C.J., and White, J., dissenting from denial of certiorari), at 4. Furthermore, the board does not have the constitutional competence to make a finding that justifies the use of a racia. classification for remedial purposes. Like the Regents in Bakke, the 3oard's "mission is education, not the formulation of any legislative policy or the adjudication of particular claims of illegality." Bakke, supra, 438 U.S. at 309 (opinion of Powell, J.). Factfinding by a state or local entity also cannot be equated with that of Congress because, among other things, the states are not granted the enforcement pcwer under Section 5 or the Fourteenth Amendment that many members of the Court found important in upholding the Act of Congress challenged m Fullilove. See 443 U.S. at 476-478, 483, 490-491 (plurality o d inion; id. at 499-502 (opinion of Powell, J.); see also Hampton v. Mow Sun Wonc, 426 U.S. 88 (1976); 3ushey, dissenting slip op. at 4. A court of equity may of course make a finding of racial discrimination, but no such finding could be made on the record in this case. The lower courts relied exclusively on statistics showing that there was a difference between the percentage of minority teachers and students during a brief span of years more than a decade ago. This difference, however, might have resulted from any of numerous innocent causes and unquestionably does not show the discriminatory intent needed to establish an ocual Protection Clause violation. Hazelwood School District v. United States, 433 U.S. at 299, 308 (1977); Village of Arlington Heights Metropolitan Housing Development Core., 429 U.S. 252, 270 (1977); Washington v . Dav i s , 426 U.S. 229, 243 (1976); Jancwiak v . City of South Bend, 750 F.2c 557, 564 (7th Cir. 1985). More fundamentally, as we have shown, even a finding that there had been oast discrimination against some individuals would not suooert a ca t rricai racial and ethnic oreferer.ee such as 33 that contained in the Jackson agreement. No findings/ then, can justify the challenged Jackson measure. Even if the board or lower courts had found a constitutional violation (and they did not) and even if they were to find such a violation on remand (and they could not on the present record) the Jackson quota could not be supported. A clear ruling by the Court on this issue would avoid pointless proceedings on remand and provide much needed guidance to lower courts struggling with similar problems. CONCLUSION For the foregoing reasons, the judgment below should be reversed. Respectfully submitted. CHARLES FRIED Acting Solicitor General WM. BRADFORD REYNOLDS Assistant Attorney General CHARLES J. COOPER DeDutv Assistant Attorney General SAMUEL A. ALITO, JR. Assistant to the Solicitor General WALTER W. 3ARNETT DAVID K. FLYNN MICHAEL CARVIN Attorneys JUNE :935