Correspondence from Tegeler to Westerman Re: The Issue of Causation in Sheff v. O'Neill
Working File
July 25, 1991

60 pages
Cite this item
-
Case Files, Sheff v. O'Neill Hardbacks. Correspondence from Tegeler to Westerman Re: The Issue of Causation in Sheff v. O'Neill, 1991. 958afb2e-a446-f011-877a-0022482c18b0. LDF Archives, Thurgood Marshall Institute. https://ldfrecollection.org/archives/archives-search/archives-item/848a7d61-d9e3-4ce2-a680-b9071fe59afe/correspondence-from-tegeler-to-westerman-re-the-issue-of-causation-in-sheff-v-oneill. Accessed October 19, 2025.
Copied!
Philip D. Tegeler Connecticut Civil Liberties Union Gayl S. Westerman Professor of Law The Issue of Causation in Sheff v. O'Neil July: 25, 1991 Issue Presented: In a desegregation suit brought under the Connecticut state Constitution, particularly one seeking an interdistrict remedy, is plaintiff barred from proceeding without proof that affirmative acts of the state "caused" the condition of segregation existing in the Hartford public schools and those of its surrounding suburbs? Discussion The issue of causation is but a sub-set of the larger question of assessing government responsibility for constitutional violations. There is little doubt that under the current approach to this question taken by federal courts under the fourteenth amendment, plaintiffs would be required to show state action as well as discriminatory motive/intent on the part of state agencies as causing or at least significantly contributing to the segregated condition existing in the public schools of Hartford and its surrounding suburbs. (See Keyes, Milliken, Washington v. Davis and progeny). It is hardly surprising that all cases cited by the defendants to support their assertion that plaintiffs are barred in their claim without proof of causation are federal cases decided by the U. S. Supreme Court under the equal protection clause of the fourteenth amendment. No support can be found for this assertion, however, under Connecticut law. Instead, defendants rely on federal law combined with a aunber of now discredited precedents in Connecticut case law which appear to support the notion that federal and state equal protection provisions have "like meaning and impose similar limitations." Defendants must surely realize that the notion that states courts are bound to apply federal constitutional interpretation standards has been repeatedly rejected by Connecticut courts, particularly since the U. S. Supreme Court adopted a discriminatory intent/causation standard to equal protection cases in the mid-seventies. Two cases in particular, Fasulo Vv. Arafeh, 173 Conn. 473 (1977) and Horton v. Meskill, 172 Conn. 615 (1977) (Horton I), have recognized the "primary independent vitality of the provisions of our own constitution," Horton I, 172 Conn. at 641, and have clearly indicated that state and federal provisions do not have to be read with like meaning and limitations. Although Connecticut courts have sometimes inserted the old "like meaning" language into current cases, the term now stands for the proposition that the Connecticut Constitution "shares but is not limited by the content of its federal counterpart." - Fasulo v. Arafeh, 173 Conn. 473, 475 (1977). As to the issue of causation itself, the lesson of Fasulo also seems clear: when the state impinges on a fundamental right in any manner, whether or not the circumstances which cause the infringement are of the state's own creation, the state bears the burden of justifying the intrusion. Although a due process case, Fasulo illustrates the willingness of Connecticut courts to depart from federal jurisprudence in effectuating state constitutional rights. Connecticut courts have consistently expanded protection of civil rights under Connecticut constitutional provisions beyond that offered by their federal counterparts, most notably in Horton v. Meskill, 172 Conn. 473 (1977) (rejecting the approach taken by the U. S. Supreme Court in Rodriquez and finding a fundamental right to education violated by state school finance laws); in Doe v. Maher, 40 Conn. Supp. 394 (1986) (rejecting the approach taken by the U. S. Supreme Court in Harris v. McRae and striking down regulation restricting right to medicaid payment for abortions under the state due process clause); in State v. Kimbro, 496 A.2d 498 (Conn. 1985) (rejecting the federal "Gates rule" on probable cause justifying search and seizure); in State v. Davis, 506 A.2d (Conn. 1986) (setting forth an independent Connecticut rule on the ultimate right to call a witness under Article first, § 8); in Griswold Thin, Inc. v. State, 441 A.24 16 (Conn. 1981) (expanding state protection of religious freedom) ; in State v. Saidel, 159 Conn. 96 (1970) and State v. Licari, 153 Conn. 127 (1965) (enlarging protections against unreasonable searches and seizures); and others. In State v. Dukes, 547 A.2d 10, 18 (Conn. 1988), the Connecticut Supreme Court, citing State Vv. Stoddard, State v. Jarzbek, State v. Scully, State v. Couture (cites omitted) and others in addition to Horton I and Fasulo, reaffirmed that although Connecticut courts are free to follow the lead of the federal courts at their discretion, "this court has never considered itself bound to adopt the federal interpretation in interpreting the Connecticut Constitution . . . . [i]t is this court's duty to interpret and enforce our constitution . . . . Thus, in a proper case, 'the law of the land' may not, in state constitutional context, also be 'the law of the state of Connecticut.'" State v. Dukes, 547 A.2d4 10, 19 (Conn. 1988). This trend in constitutional adjudication in Connecticut is part of a larger trend nationwide which finds many state supreme courts interpreting their state constitutions to afford more expansive protection to their citizens than is afforded under the federal constitution. See, e.9., Reeves v. State, 599 P.2d 727 (Alaska 1979); State v. Sporleder, 666 P.2d 135 (Colo. 1983); Bierkamp v. Rogers, 293 N.W.2d 577 (Iowa 1980); People Vv. Hoshowski, 108 Mich. App. 321, 310 N.W.2d 228 (1981); People Vv. Williams, 93 Misc.2d 93, 402 N.Y.S.2d 289 (1978); State Vv. Flores, 280 or 273, 570 P.2d 965 (1977); People v. Neville, 346 N.W.2d 425 (S.D. 1984); Miller v. State, 584 S.W.2d 758 (Tenn. 1979); State v. Ringer, 100 Wash. 2d 686, 674 P.2d 1240 (1983); §:1 . » Helena Elementary School Dist. v. State, 769 P.2d 684 (Mont. 1989); Stout v. Grand Prairie Ind. School Dist., 733 S.W.2d 290 (Tex. Ct. App. 1987); Edgewood Indep. School Dist. v. Kirby, 777 S.W.2d 391 (Tex. 1989); Jenkins v. Township of Morris School Dist., 279 A.24 619 (N.J. 1971); Booker v. Bd. of Educ. Plainsfied, 45 N.J. 161 (1965); and others. This trend is well- documented in the literature. See Developments in the Law--The Interpretation of State Constitutional Rights, 95 Harv. L. Rev. 1324 (1982); Brennan, State Constitutions and the Protection of Individual Rights, 90 Harv. L. Rev. 489 (1977). As undeniable as this trend may be, I believe that due to the strong rejection of an interdistrict remedy by the U. S. Supreme Court in Milliken, which relies in turn on the discriminatory intent/causation requirement for equal protection cases announced in Keyes, Washington v. Davis, and progeny, the defendant's argument that plaintiff's claim is barred without proof of state action which caused the segregated condition to exist and, further, that such a causal connection can only be established by showing defendant's discriminatory intent or expectation of harm, see Memorandum in Support of Defendant's Motion to Strike, at 33, may be more difficult to oppose than might be hoped. State courts, Connecticut included, still pay lip service, at least, to the notion that U. S. Supreme Court opinions are "persuasive authority" for state constitutional interpretations, and the issue of interdistrict remedies in desegregation cases has been a topic of heated debate between and among constitutional scholars since the decision in Milliken I was announced in 1973. (For an exhaustive review of most of these divergent views, see Liebman, Desegregating Politics: 'All-Out' School Desegregation Explained, 90 Colum. L. Rev. 1463- 1664 (1990)). Both sides in the current conflict over the Hartford area schools will be able to find ample support for their arguments in re: intent/causation in this literature. If the Court decides to follow the federal approach in assessing government responsibility and requires a showing of state action/intent/causation, I believe you are well prepared in this regard and may prevail even in obtaining an interdistrict remedy. A few lower federal courts have ordered such remedies since 1973 and the U. S. Supreme Court did so in Columbus Board of Education v. Penick, 443 U.S. 449 (1979) and Dayton Board of Education v. Brinkman, 443 U.S. 526 (1979) by, arguably, broadening the Keyes standard somewhat and taking note of precisely the kind of evidence which you propose to introduce. Nevertheless, I agree that by far the best result would be Connecticut's adopting its own approach under state law unburdened by these threshold tests. The majority opinions of the Connecticut courts in Horton, Fasulo and_Maher, as well as the forceful dissent by Justice Peters in Cologne v. Westfarms Associates, 469 A.2d 1201, 1211 (Conn. 1984) (arguing that there is no textual basis for a state action requirement under the state constitution, but "if we are to import [one] into the Connecticut Constitution, we must ‘t » & recognize that its contours will necessarily differ from the state action concept that has developed under the Constitution of the United States," id. at 1218, give me a basis for guarded optimism that the court will be amenable to an approach to desegregation under the Connecticut Constitution that differs markedly from that taken by the U. S. Supreme Court in Milliken - - i.e., that "Sheff is to Milliken as Horton is to Rodriquez". In my opinion, an excellent basis for a distinctive Connecticut approach to desegregation has already been created by the Connecticut Supreme Court in Horton I. In that case, the court, while retaining the "tiers of scrutiny" aspect of federal equal protection jurisprudence (later changed somewhat under Horton IIT), nevertheless declined to adopt a discriminatory intent and/or causation threshold test. At most, the court appears to have adopted an "effects" test which was satisfied in that case by a showing that a specific condition, i.e., inequity in school financing, which has "resulted" from delegating legislation may constitute a violation by the state of both the equal protection clauses of the Connecticut Constitution as well as the affirmative duty to provide for equal educational opportunity by "rappropriate’' legislation." Horton I, 172 Conn. at 649. It seems a very short step from this language to the approach which you have adopted in Sheff, i.e., that, once again, delegating legislation by the state has "resulted" in school district boundaries which have made racially balanced schools, mandated by state law as essential to equal educational opportunity, an impossibility in metropolitan areas such as Hartford and its surrounding towns. The question is, how to encourage the court to take this step? There are several avenues of argumentation which might prove helpful in lending support to your argument that a "causation" requirement in any of its various forms does not, and, further, should not exist under Connecticut constitutional jurisprudence. I have set forth some of these avenues for you in the following memorandum which, in outline form, makes these points: l. Connecticut courts should not adopt the federal standard in school desegregation cases because: The current federal approach to assessment of government responsibility in school desegregation cases is not mandated by the U. S. Constitution or prior federal case law; is based on flawed legal theory; and is incapable of providing a satisfactory remedy to metropolitan-wide segregation. The federal approach is based on federalist and other institutional concerns which do not limit the power of Connecticut courts to resolve issues under the Connecticut Constitution. These and other differences in the two systems of y ! % adjudication militate in favor of an independent Connecticut approach which does not reflect the federal model. 2. Connecticut courts should develop an independent approach to school desegregation cases under the Connecticut state Constitution because: a. A clear understanding of the problems to be remedied demands an effects-based jurisprudence focused on segregative condition. Such an approach is fully supported by the express language of the Connecticut Constitution and Connecticut case law. b. A per se approach to segregative condition under the Connecticut Constitution is supported by empirical research studies which unequivocally affirm the value of racially balanced schools to minority and white students alike, to their parents, and to the society at large. Deprivation of an opportunity to attend such schools in metropolitan areas such as Hartford and its surrounding suburbs is a per se denial of the fundamental right to equal educational opportunity, mandated by Horton I. 1. Connecticut courts should not adopt the federal standard in school desegregation cases because: The current federal approach to assessment of government responsibility in school desegregation cases is not mandated by the U. S. Constitution or prior federal case law; is based on a flawed legal theory; and is incapable of providing a satisfactory remedv to metropolitan-wide segregation. Two important cases decided by the U. S. Supreme Court in the early seventies seemed to point the way toward an enlightened school desegregation doctrine in which courts moved away from condemning only those cases of segregation where assignments were made on the basis of race to a result-oriented approach that focused on the segregated patterns themselves. Fiss, The Charlotte-Mecklenburg Case - Its Significance for Northern School Desegregation, 38 U. Chi. L. Rev. 697 (1971). In Green v. New Kent County School Board, 391 U.S. 430 (1968), the U. S. Supreme Court invalidated a presumedly race-neutral student assignment plan based on "freedom-of-choice", where the result of the plan was continued racial segregation. The Court expanded on this approach in Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Board of Education, 402 U.S. 1 (1971), by declaring "geographic proximity" an 10 impermissible basis for student assignment, again, because the plan did not "work" in diminishing the segregated condition of the schools, and by ordering an interdistrict remedy in which the greatest degree of actual desegregation must be achieved. Many commentators at the time would have agreed with Fiss that "the net effect of Charlotte-Mecklenburqg is to move school desegregation doctrine further along the continuum toward a result oriented approach . . . [in] retrospect, Charlotte- Mecklenburg will then be viewed, like Green, as a way station to the adoption of a general approach to school desegregation which, by focusing on the segregated patterns themselves, is more responsive to the school desegregation of the North." Fiss, supra at 704-705. Two factors, one internal and the other external, conspired against the continuation of this trend. The Swann case itself, though result-oriented in part and enormously productive in terms of remedy (Charlotte-Mecklenburg is now widely seen as one of the most successful of court-ordered desegregation plans), carried within it the seeds of a doctrinal trend which veered away from a focus on segregated condition alone and toward a focus on past discriminatory practices as forming a causal link to segregated conditions in the present. Fiss himself noted the danger in this element of the Court's approach but discounted it for two reasons: first, he believed that the predominant concern of the Court was the segregated pattern of school attendance, otherwise such an "all-out" remedy could not be defended. Second, the Court's theory of causation itself seemed contrived. Although discriminatory practices had undeniably played a role in the past, the Court did not attempt to determine the degree to which such practices had contributed to the present condition. In Fiss' words, the Court had merely used past discrimination/causation as a "trigger . . . for a cannon", i.e., the all-out desegregation remedy, as well as a way to preserve continuity with Brown and add a moral foundation for the decision. Id. at 705. Fiss predicted that the result-oriented language of Swann would outlive the past discrimination/causal link requirement, largely because the Supreme Court would be unable to treat segregated conditions in northern and southern schools differently: A complicated analysis of causation might . . . serve to justify the differential treatment afforded these otherwise identical patterns. But such an analysis is not likely to be understood or believed by most people. And no National institutions can afford to be unresponsive to the popular pressures likely to be engendered by an appearance of differential treatment of certain regions of the county. Fiss, supra pg. 10, at 705. These confident predictions of a trend toward a result- oriented jurisprudence in school desegregation cases seemed well- founded immediately following Swann. Lower federal courts, while paying heed to the discriminatory intent/causal link elements of the Court's decision, found these requirements to be easily satisfied in a variety of creative ways, such as holding the government responsible for the reasonably foreseeable and 2 » ' % avoidable results of its actions or for its failure to act when under a duty to do so, even if no actual causal link to discriminatory animus could be proved. Courts often adopted the burden shifting approach taken in Swann to force the state, once a segregated condition had been shown to exist by plaintiff, to prove that its actions had not caused that condition to be created or maintained. This jurisprudential trend might have continued had not an external factor intervened in the form of process-oriented constitutional theorists (Ely, Brest, and others) who maintained that in a democratic society, essentially nondemocratic institutions such as courts should avoid reviewing the substance or the fairness of governmental decisionmaking and should intervene only if the process of the decision making had become adulterated in some way. See Ortiz, The Myth of Intent in Equal Protection Cases, 41 Stan. L. Rev. 1105, 1105 (1989). In equal protection terms, this adulteration was seen as resulting from forbidden discriminatory motivations. Id. at 1106. The rapid ascendancy of process-based theories in the scholarly literature coincided with the beginning of a period of retrenchment in the Supreme Court which occurred precisely at the time the Court decided the first "northern" school desegregation case in 1973. In Keyes v. School District No. 1, Denver, Colorado, 411 U.S. 189 (1973), the Court held that the desegregation remedies approved in Swann were equally applicable to northern school districts which had never been segregated by law, but only where local a3. officials had pursued deliberately segregative policies. Keyes was followed by Milliken v. Bradley (Milliken I), 418 U.S. 717 (1974), in which the Supreme Court rejected a metropolitan-wide remedy for Detroit, holding that "it must be shown that racially discriminatory acts of the state or local school districts, or of a single school district, have been a substantial cause of interdistrict segregation." Id. at 744-45. This rejection left uncorrected the dual school system and the vestiges of school segregation which the district court had found to exist in Detroit, vestiges which the Supreme Court had ordered removed "root and branch" throughout South. The final pieces of the current Court's equal protection doctrine were put into place with three cases which left no doubt as to the emerging doctrinal trend: Washington v. Davis, 426 U.S. 229 (1976), which held that in the absence of a racially discriminatory motive or purpose, a facially neutral governmental action, such as the use of screening tests in hiring, which has an adverse racial impact will not be subject to strict scrutiny; Village of Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Housing Development Corp., 429 U.S. 252 (1977), which held that race must be shown to be a motivating factor in the refusal to rezone land for low- income housing and disproportionate impact alone would not satisfy the intent standard; and Personnel Administrator v. Feeney, 442 U.S. 256 (1979), in which the Court refused to import into equal protection jurisprudence the familiar doctrine that a person intends the natural and foreseeable consequences of her 14 voluntary actions, a doctrine which had been used productively by lower federal courts in satisfying the intent/causation requirement in school desegregation cases. These decisions have not been totally fatal to school desegregation. The Court has ordered desegregation plans implemented in both Dayton, Dayton Board of Education v. Brinkman (Dayton II), 443 U.S. 526 (1979) and Columbus, Columbus Board of Education v. Penick, 443 U.S. 449 (1979), on grounds which, it could be argued, relaxed the Keyes discriminatory intent/causation standard to some degree while retaining it doctrinally. Nevertheless, all commentators, whether in favor of an intent/causation requirement or adamantly opposed, agree that such a standard has made it very difficult for plaintiffs to prevail in school desegregation cases, and almost impossible to prevail in those involving metropolitan-wide segregation of the type currently existing in Hartford and its surrounding suburbs. Many commentators have criticized the Supreme Court's use of a discriminatory intent/causation requirement in school desegregation cases which, in addition to other rationales often used to limit the reach of judicial remedies, such as the de jure - de facto distinction, federalism concerns, and respect for school district lines and local control, has become a formidable obstacle to the invalidation of public policies alleged to violate the fourteenth amendment. See Goodman, De facto School Segregation: A Constitutional and Empirical Analysis, 60 Cal. L. Rev. 275 (1972); Fiss, The Fate of an Idea Whose Time Has Come: 15 Antidiscrimination Law in the Second Decade after Brown v. Board of Education, 41 U. Chi. L. Rev. 742 (1974); Binion, Intent and Equal Protection: A Reconsideration, Sup. Ct. Rev. 397 (1983); L. H. Tribe, American Constitutional law (2d Ed.) (1988); Tribe, The Puzzling Persistence of Process-Based Constitutional Theories, 89 Yale L.J. 1063 (1980); Tribe, The Curvature of Constitutional Space: What Lawvers Can Learn From Modern Physics," 103 Harv. L. Rev. 1 (1989); Stein, Attacking School Desegregation Root and Branch, 99 Yale L.J. 1983 (1990); See also Ortiz and Liebman, supra. Most if not all of these legal scholars would agree that such a standard is in no way implied or required by the general language of the equal protection clause of the fourteenth amendment. Nor was it required under prior federal case law which in general held intent to be irrelevant in equal protection cases. See, e.qg., Palmer v. Thompson, 403 U.S. 217, 224 (1971) ("[N]o case in this court has held that a legislative act may violate equal protection solely because of the motivations of the men who voted for it"). Other explanations must therefore be provided for such a radical change of course. Ortiz' theory is that several factors combined to produce the Court's approach to equal protection under the fourteen amendment. By the early seventies, the Court had so thoroughly fleshed-out its "tiers of scrutiny" jurisprudence that results in equal protection cases had become predictable. Once the groups deserving of strict scrutiny had been put in place, the key 16 question became identifying the group targeted by the governmental decision. This was a fairly simple task as long as laws discriminated on their face against protected groups. When government officials began to use "proxy" classifications, i.e., classifications such as wealth and education which appear facially neutral but which correlate with race and other protected classifications, the Court needed an intent requirement to uncover these covert, proxy classifications in order to know how to proceed with their tiers of scrutiny analysis. Ortiz, supra p. 13, at 1117-1119. This development coincided with the ascendancy of process-based theories in constitutional law, discussed supra, which required a show of intentional discrimination in the decisionmaking process in order to justify court intervention. As necessary or as laudable as such a doctrinal development may have been, Ortiz argues that it has not served its purpose and is in fact applied differently depending on the type of case being adjudicated. In equal protection cases involving housing and employment, a plaintiff prevails only with absolute proof of discriminatory motive, an approach which protects the cohort classifications of wealth and education by which such benefits are traditionally allocated. In cases involving voting and jury selection, benefits not traditionally allocated by wealth and education, discriminatory intent can be considered the "cause" of an adverse impact by showing the impact on an identifiable group combined with either the susceptibility of the selection process 17 to manipulation (jury selection cases) or discrimination in other areas of life (voting cases). Id. at 1135. It is in the school desegregation cases that the intent/causation requirement has been most bizarrely applied. At the initial phase of litigation, plaintiffs must still show evidence of discriminatory motivation at some time from Brown I on. Once that has been accomplished by plaintiffs, which is increasingly hard to do as motivations become more and more attenuated and causal links to current segregated conditions become all but impossible to discern, the state can rebut such evidence only with a compelling justification for segregation, which no state has ever done. Should a plaintiff prevail in establishing liability, the state is under an affirmative duty to achieve a unitary system, and its efforts in this regard are judged solely on the basis of effect. Once unitariness has been achieved and the district court has relinquished its jurisdiction over the case, however, should resegregation occur, plaintiffs must now carry the burden of showing actual discriminatory motivation in the current decisionmaking process much as plaintiffs are required to do in housing and employment cases discussed above. Id. at 1135-1140. Needless to say, this approach has not only made the problem of metropolitan-wide segregation very difficult to remedy but has also made it virtually impossible to attack de facto resegregation in areas where the original problem had once been alleviated. There are other problems inherent in such an approach, not 18 the least of which is its failure to properly take note of the effect of unconscious racism in the decision-making process. Lawrence, see Lawrence, The Id, the Ego, and Equal Protection: Reckoning with Unconscious Racism, 39 Stan. L. Rev. 317 (1987) has said: [T]raditional notions of intent do not reflect the fact that decisions about racial matters are influenced in large part by factors that can be characterized as neither intentional . . . nor unintentional . . . a large part of the behavior that produces racial discrimination is influenced by unconscious racial motivation. | Id. at 322. Lawrence argues that Americans share a common cultural heritage in which racism has played a dominant role. Out of this has developed a common cultural belief system containing certain tacit understandings of which we are largely unaware. Because they are so widespread in society and are never, or rarely, directly taught, these beliefs and understandings are less likely to be experienced at the conscious level, and even if they do surface occasionally, are quickly refused recognition because they conflict with a shared moral code which rejects such thoughts as "racist". Lawrence continues: In short, requiring proof of conscious or intentional motivation as a prerequisite to constitutional recognition that a decision is race-dependent ignores much of what we understand about how the human mind works . . . . The equal protection clause requires the elimination of governmental decisions that take race into account without good and important reasons. Therefore, equal protection doctrine must find a way to come to grips with unconscious racism. gd. at 322. 19 Tribe has criticized the doctrine as applied in school desegregation cases on the same grounds. Rather than contracting the judicial role in cases of de facto segregation, Tribe believes the arguments in favor of expanding it are much more compelling, precisely because the exact motivations, purposes, intentions and causes in such cases are so difficult to discern: The harms of both de facto and de jure discrimination are similar if not identical: racially specific harm to members of politically less-powerful minority groups, with discriminatory intent much more often present than provable, and with even truly unintended racial consequences reflecting unconscious bias and blindness traceable to a legacy of racial subordination initially decreed by law. L. H. Tribe, supra p.:16, at 1500. Tribe contends that until our society's widespread racial prejudice recedes and minority members gain power enough to affect decisions vital to the exercise of their fundamental rights, [JJudicially compelled integration may be the only acceptable response to the high probability of governmental prejudice and corruption behind all segregation. Id, at 1500. See also Goodman, supra p. 15; and Dworkin, Social Sciences and Constitutional Rights: The Consequences of Uncertainty, 6 3. of L. and Bduc. 3 (1977). Other commentators have criticized the current federal approach on the grounds that it has developed from a form of legal analysis which seeks to identify wrongdoers and hold them responsible for "causing" harm to a protected group. Tribe has identified the problem as one resulting from reliance on "antidiscrimination" as the mediating principle underlying the 20 equal protection clause. L. H. Tribe, supra p. 16, at 1514. The problem is that discrimination is an act based on prejudice, and its essential elements are therefore an actor and an action based on invidious grounds. Id. at 1515. When mediated by an antidiscrimination principle, the fourteenth amendment then becomes a tool for overturning acts motivated by racial or other bias. Because the focus is on the "perpetrator", this leads inexorably to the state action, discriminatory intent, and causation standards currently employed and, therefore, to the results in Washington v. Davis, Milliken and other cases. In each case, Tribe asserts, the Supreme Court has noted the disparate, harmful effect on the victim and then focused on the intent of the perpetrator rather than the impact. Tribe suggests that at the present stage, when the problems have become so entrenched that intent/causation is almost impossible to prove, a far better mediator for equal protection purposes would be the principle of antisubjugation which aims not at preventing discriminatory acts of wrongdoers but rather at breaking down legally created or legally reinforced systems which treat some people as second class citizens. L. H. Tribe, supra p. 16, at 1515. (See infra for an application of such an approach to equal protection under the Connecticut Constitution). Liebman raises similar concerns. He describes the Court's move in desegregation cases from reliance on equal educational opportunity or integration theories in the fifties and sixties, which tended to focus on remedying the effects of government 21 decisionmaking, to the what he terms the "Correction Theory", Liebman, supra p. 6, at 1501, which focuses on the evil acts of wrongdoers. The moral imperative of the Correction Theory is identical to that which motivates the law of torts, i.e., a "deep sense of common law morality that one who hurts another should compensate him." Id. In the desegregation context, this theory translates into the moral claim that purposeful discrimination is a wrong whose effects must be eliminated. Liebman argues that the tort analogy, which fits in neatly with process-based theories discussed above, has been appealing to courts because it is "simple, individualistic, and by hypothesis nonredistributive." Id. Ultimately, however, private law solutions to public law problems are inherently unsatisfying and ineffective. In particular, they fail to respond satisfactorily to "insidiously prevalent, decades-long, metropolitan-wide, multi-disciplinary and variously harmful public racial discrimination" for the same reasons that private law compensatory tort approaches fail to respond satisfactorily to mass toxic disasters. Id. at 1518. Liebman draws convincing analogies between the two cases. He argues that the complicated character and the massive scale of the problem in both scenarios cause the correctively critical prerequisites of an identifiable plaintiff and an identifiable defendant to elude proof, notwithstanding the fact that "wrongdoers" have undoubtedly visited harms on large numbers of plaintiffs. As a result, in both the mass toxic tort and school 22 segregation contexts, the supposed moral integrity of the compensatory system evaporates. d. at 1519. Tort scholars, see P. Schuck, Agent Orange on Trial: Mass Toxic Disasters in the Courts (1986) (distinguishing private law and public law toxic tort litigation), have drawn attention to the problems of victims of cancer who can prove beyond doubt their exposure to a toxic agent that is known to increase the incidence of cancer in the population but which may be only one of many "causes" of the victims' cancers. Typically, these plaintiffs can also show that the agent was produced at a given time by one or several chemical companies, but ultimately cannot prove which. Leibman argues that the case of residentially and educationally segregated minority children is similar, in that they can show "exposure" to myriad acts of school, housing and other government officials, any one of which, in addition to a like-myriad of "neutral" factors, may have "caused" the segregation. Liebman sees the most problematic feature of both mass toxic tort and desegregation litigation to be the difficulty of proving specific causation of injuries that cannot be proven to be either "substance- or discrimination-specific." Liebman, supra p. 6, at 1519. A further problem is linking the plaintiffs' provable harms, known to have been "caused" by some one or some group of defendants, to the defendant who can be found "responsible" under the current preponderance of the evidence rule. Liebman concludes that as in toxic torts, the traditional 23 tort approach is not an effective legal response to the polycentric problems posed by school desegregation cases but is instead "an ostrich-like avoidance of them." Id. at 1521. Moreover, the current public law approach being taken to some mass toxic torts, using a classwide solution which relies on proportional liability (e.g., market share) and probabilistic proof of causation, is not transportable to the school desegregation context; and even if it were, continued reliance on a tort model makes even less sense when the version of that model chosen for application completely vitiates the moral imperative of the Correction Theory -- i.e., holding a specific wrongdoer liable for the specific harm "caused" in the most fundamental way. Liebman favors the abandonment of the Correction Theory in federal jurisprudence, but, curiously, argues for the retention of some form of the intent standard, even though he admits that to do so makes the problem of metropolitan-wide segregation nearly impossible to resolve. Id. at 1663. Many commentators have argued that it would be better by far to abandon the tort model completely as having failed to eliminate a society-wide harm in any but the most ad hoc and arbitrary fashion. Under the current federal approach, the Court appears to be saying to plaintiffs, "If you can prove by a preponderance of the evidence that a given actor's discriminatory animus during the decisionmaking process caused the harm you are currently suffering, in an era in which a reluctant society is ever more skillful at disguising such animus and obliterating the 24 causal links, then we will use the full force of declaratory and injunctive relief to remedy your suffering. If you fail to surmount this burden, however, we must turn a blind eye to your suffering" and, in some cases, actually deny that it exists, thereby legitimating it. Tribe has been a harsh critic of that particular result of the current federal approach: A corollary of responsible modernism is to admit that we can see more than we can do. But this does not mean that we should lie about what we see. Tribe, supra p. 16, at 38. Tribe argues that by utilizing a reference point of detached neutrality to selectively reach in to society, make a few "fine- tuning adjustments", and step back out, the federal courts are ignoring the lesson of modern quantum mechanics which tells us that the act of observing always affects what is being observed, and that the observer is never really "detached" from the system being studied. Id. at 13. The results courts announce, the way they view the legal terrain, and what they say about it have continuing effects that reshape the nature of what the courts initially undertook to review. Id. at 20. Fiss has also observed the power of a court's response to a given claim to reshape both the legal and societal framework from which the claim arose: Shrouded in the mantle of the Constitution, dedicated to the reasoned elaboration of our communal ideals, courts have a unique capacity to create the terms of their own legitimacy . . . . The moral status of a claim may derive from its legal recognition: morality shaped the judgment in Brown v. Board of Education and 25 that judgment then shaped our morality. O. M. Fiss, The Civil Rights Injunction 95 (1978). Tribe points out that the legal landscape that creates the perception that white flight is an inherently private matter beyond the scope of law and that the resulting ghettoization of inner cities is therefore inevitable has itself been explicitly shaped by Supreme Court decisions. Pierce v. Society of Sisters, Swann, Milliken, and even Brown I (due to its original focus on the school district rather than the state as the responsible party) read together say in effect that white parents have the right to keep their children in white, affluent classes by moving to the suburbs. Tribe, supra p.16, at 27. Fiss has also recognized that the clear legitimating message of a state's rigid adherence to geographic criteria for school attendance is to say to the parent who does not want her children to attend an integrated school, your desire can be fulfilled simply by moving to a white neighborhood. Fiss, Racial Imbalance in the Public Schools: The Constitutional Concepts, 78 Harv. L. Rev. 564 (1965) . Criticizing the Supreme Court's decision in Milliken as a failure to create a rights-remedy dialogue in society which might have eventually located a solution to the problem of metropolitan-wide segregation, Tribe says: Even if it would have had no impact on judicial remedies, a judicial proclamation that inner-city ghettoization was constitutionally infirm might have avoided legitimating this nation-wide travesty. Had the Court exerted the one thing it clearly can control -- its rights declaration powers -- to 26 w» : A recognize the role of law and of state action in creating ghettoization, the Court could at least have created positive social and political tension, the sort of tension that makes kids grow up thinking that something is wrong, instead of inevitable, about ghettoization. Tribe, supra p.16, at 30. Counselling abandonment of the current federal approach to equal protection, Tribe suggests that the Court should be much more willing than it has been to recognize government responsibility for the "racially separationist consequences of neutrally motivated acts." Id. at 33. Such recognition, he continues, demands less an effort by courts to uncover the "hidden levers, gears, or forces" that causally link governmental action to objective effects than an attempt to "feel the contours of the world government has built -- and to sense what those contours mean for those who might be trapped or excluded by them." Id. at 39. To announce that government bears no responsibility for problems it has not intended to cause is to legitimate both the governmental actions and their effects and, worse, to relieve both governmental and non-governmental actors, as well as other remedial fora such as state courts, executives, and legislatures, of the responsibility for resolving these problems. Id. at 33-34, citing Sager, Fair Measure: The legal Status of Under-Enforced Constitutional Norms, 91 Harv. L. Rev. 1212 (1978). A far better outcome, in Tribe's view, would be a court's admission that a protected group has been impermissibly harmed but this court has no way to remedy it, than to say no harm has been done or that government is not responsible for 27 finding a remedy. Arguing for a theory of government responsibility based on the government's ability to avoid harmful effects rather than on its intent to cause such effects, Tribe says: We may all be engulfed by, and dependent upon, the structure of the law, but we are not all rendered equally vulnerable by it. If the special dependance upon the law and its omissions that is experienced by the most vulnerable among us could be dismissed as irrelevant because it was not directly created by any state force targeting such individuals, their heightened dependence might be seen as irrelevant. But if the systemic vulnerability of some . . . is instead regarded as centrally relevant to how the law's shape should be understood, then one is more likely to ask whether the legal system's failure to do more for such persons might not work an unconstitutional deprivation of their rights. Id. at 13, (emphasis added). b. The federal approach is based on federalist and other institutional concerns which do not limit the power of Connecticut courts to resolve issues under the Connecticut Constitution. These and other differences in the two systems of adjudication militate in favor of an independent Connecticut approach which does not reflect the federal model. The federal courts comprise a crucial bulwark against evulsive depredation of constitutional values; but against scattered erosion they are relatively powerless. Sager, supra p. 27, at 122s. Like Sager, other commentators (see, e.g., L. H. Tribe, supra p. 16, at 1513) have observed that while federal courts 28 have been effective against overt apartheid -- Jim Crow and "white's only" signs -- the "contemporary symptoms of inertial and unconscious prejudice are more subtle" and have proven much more difficult to eradicate. The federal courts have been retarded in their eradication efforts by many limitations, some institutional, some doctrinally self-imposed, which do not apply to state courts. The current trend, noted above, of independent state constitutional interpretations which carve out additional protections to those offered under the fourteenth amendment has led to a growing perception among judges and legal scholars that Supreme Court decisions, which we have tended to consider as the end of the constitutional decisionmaking process, represent instead the mid-point of an evolving system in which, if the decision strikes down the action complained of, it sets a federal minimum but if it upholds the action as constitutional, it may lead to a series of "second-looks" by state decisionmakers in which Supreme Court decisions no longer carry presumptive validity. Williams, In the Supreme Court's Shadow: Legitimacy of State Rejection of the Supreme Court's Reasoning and Result, 35 S.C.L. Rev. 353 (1984); See also Brennan, supra p. 5; Mosk, The Law of the Next Century: The State Courts in American law: The Third Century, 213, 220-25 (B. Schwartz ed. 1976)). There is now an extensive literature favoring this trend as well as numerous court decisions, both state and federal, which attest to its validity. One justification for this evolving pattern is found in the 29 fact that state courts simply are not bound by the same institutional limitations which, whether implicitly (Milliken) or explicitly (Rodriquez) expressed, often form the basis for a federal decision. The first of these limitations is the Court's concern for federalism, especially in equal protection cases. See L. H. Tribe, supra p. 16, at 1510-12. Tribe believes that the Supreme Court's deep reservations about the efficacy and legitimacy of intrusive federal injunctive remedies lie at the base of their decisions in cases involving a discriminatory intent/causation requirement. In each case, the remedies sought posed the risk that the federal court would become deeply enmeshed in the machinery of state and local government, an institutional concern that is serious and legitimate but does not excuse the Court from ignoring the underlying problem by imposing a threshold test. In Tribe's view (discussed in part supra), rather than saying "there is no constitutional violation here because no discriminatory intent has been shown," the Court should say "there is a constitutional violation here but institutional considerations (such as our awareness of our role in the federal system) prevent us from offering a remedy." The significance of this very different message is that the problem is then passed on to other branches of government, who are equally obliged to uphold constitutional values, for resolution. Officers of state governments, regardless of branch, are not restrained by the principles of federalism that may hinder a federal court's ability, or reluctance, to enforce a decree. In 30 particular, state courts may play a role vis-a-vis the other branches of state government that differs markedly from the limited "interstitial" role of the federal courts. Id. at 1513. Presumably, Tribe would approve of the U. S. Supreme Court's approach in Rodriquez which, while denying a basis for a federal right to education under the U. S. Constitution, clearly stated that their decision was not to be viewed as placing its judicial imprimatur on the status quo and, as the Connecticut Supreme Court interpreted it in Horton I, issued a call to arms for states to resolve the issue, unburdened by the federalist concerns made explicit by the Supreme Court in that case. Horton I, 172 Conn. at 634-35. Justice Peters, dissenting in Pellegrino V. O'Neill, 193 Conn. 670, 673 (1984), expressed the idea clearly: "We are free to consider this matter unencumbered by the considerations of federalism which have led federal courts to doubt the propriety of federal intervention in the administration of state judicial systems." A second limitation on federal constitutional analysis, overlapping somewhat with federalist concerns above, is the state action requirement which federal courts have derived from the "No state shall . . ." language of the fourteenth amendment. In addition to the obvious lack of any such limiting, state-specific language in either of the equal protection provisions of the Connecticut Constitution, there is an even more fundamental reason for not importing a state action requirement into state constitutional decisionmaking: the purpose served by that 31 requirement in interpreting the federal constitution does not exist in the state context. The original purpose of the state action requirement was to shield some portion of state sovereignty from the seemingly broad reach of the fourteenth amendment. Margulies sees the requirement of state action as a misleading shorthand expression which implies a balancing of interests of the complainant with two countervailing factors: the interests of the wrongdoer and the interests of the state in resolving the matter without federal interference. The latter factor is missing in state court adjudication. Margulies, A lawyer's View of the constitution, 15 Conn. L. Rev. 107,111 (19582). Justice Peters, dissenting in Cologne v. Westfarms Associates, 469 A.2d 1201, 1211 (Conn. 1984), argues that the state action requirement was designed by the federal courts to address the demands of federalism, to create space for state regulation. Id. at 1218, citing Tribe, supra p. 16, at 1149-50. As discussed above, Peters believes there is no basis for a state action requirement under state constitutions because this "federalism component" is missing; but if the state courts should decide to devise one independently, it should not conform to federal law but be more flexible and "more readily found for a claim of racial discrimination." Id. at 1218, citing Lockwood Vv. Killian, 172 Conn. 502, 503. Justice Peters cites, Cologne, 469 A.2d at 1212-1213, numerous decisions in other state courts rejecting a state action requirement under their state 32 “« . constitutions. E.g., Robins v. Pruneyard Shopping Center, 23 Cal. 34 899 (1979), aff'd, 447 U.S. 74 (1980); State v. Schmid, 84 N.J. 535, 599-60 (1980), appeal dismissed, sub nom; Princeton Univ. v. Schmid, 455 U.S. 100 (1982); Batchelder v. Allied Stores Int'l, Inc., 388 Mass, 83, 88-89 (1983). When defendants assert, therefore, that plaintiffs in the Sheff case cannot proceed without first satisfying "the state action requirement", they are once again invoking a federal doctrine devised by federal courts for federal purposes under the fourteenth amendment. Technically, there is no state action requirement under the Connecticut or any other state constitution. In Connecticut, this assertion could be based solely on the different language in the federal and state provisions, a difference which many state courts have used persuasively to avoid implying a state action requirement into state constitutional adjudication. Williams, supra p. 29, at 369-70. But even if the language of the state and federal provisions were exactly the same, many would agree that there would be no inherent reason for state courts to read that language as imposing the same limitations as have their federal counterparts. Id. at 389-90. As Brennan has observed, supra p. 5, at 495, an increasing number of state courts have construed state constitutions and state bills of rights as guaranteeing even more protection than the federal provisions, even if identical in wording. Brennan cites several cases in New Jersey, Hawaii, Michigan, South Dakota, Maine, and other states as 33 examples of this phenomenon, id. at 499-501, and in particular these exemplary words of the California Supreme Court: "We declare that [the decision to the contrary of the United States Supreme Court] is not persuasive authority in any state prosecution in California . . . . We pause . . . to reaffirm the independent nature of the California Constitution and our responsibility to separately define and protect the rights of California citizens, despite conflicting decisions of the United States Supreme Court interpreting the Federal Constitution." Nor are U. S. Supreme Court statements in Pruneyard and other cases to the effect that state courts are free to interpret their constitutions to expand constitutional rights as they see fit the source of state power in this regard. It is now widely accepted that a state constitution is an independent source of rights, to be elaborated on its own terms. The majority opinion in Cologne v. Westfarms Associates, 469 A.2d 1201, 1206, reaffirms this principle, citing State v. Ferrell, 191 Conn. 37, 45 n.12 (1983), Griswold Inn, Inc. v. State, 183 Conn. 552, 559 n.3 (1981): Fasulo v. Arafeh, 173 Conn. 473, 475 (1977); and Horton v. Meskill, 172 Conn. 615, 641-42 (1977). Brennan agrees that federal court decisions are not the source of a state's power to interpret its own constitution, and points out further that the notion that state constitutional provisions were intended to mirror the federal does not comport with history, which reveals that the drafters of the federal Bill of Rights drew on provisions of already existing state 34 constitutions as their source. Additionally, prior to the adoption of the fourteenth amendment, the state bills of rights were independently interpreted, since the federal Bill of Rights had been held inapplicable. Therefore, Supreme Court decisions "are not, and should not be, dispositive of questions regarding rights guaranteed by counterpart provisions of state law." See Brennen, supra p. 5, at 501-502; See also generally, Brennan, The Bill of Rights and the States, in The Great Rights (E. Cohn ed. 1963). In sum, despite the obvious language differences between the Connecticut and federal equal protection provisions, the institutional limitations on federal courts which produced the state action requirement under the fourteenth amendment provide Connecticut courts with ample reason to reject a state action requirement in Connecticut equal protection cases, most fundamentally because this requirement has nothing to do with the substantive Connecticut constitutional guarantee of equality. Federal doctrine is also dictated in part by other institutional limitations which do not hamper state courts. First, U. S. Supreme Court decisions must operate in all areas of the nation and must, therefore, represent the lowest common denominator of rights protection. Second, the doctrine of selective incorporation used for applying the Bill of Rights to the states leads to questions regarding the dilution of those rights in a state context. Williams, supra p. 29, at 389. Third, "state courts that rest their decisions wholly or even 35 partly on state law need not apply federal principles of standing and justiciability that deny litigants access to the Courts." Brennan, supra p. 5, at 501. In addition to the institutional infirmities cited above, Williams has cited many functional differences between federal and state courts which militate against adopting a federal approach to a state constitutional question. First, state courts are often deeply involved in the state's policymaking process, which reflects a very different institutional position from that of the U. S. Supreme Court. Second, a state court's judicial function is often quite different. State courts perform a great deal of nonconstitutional law making, a power which federal courts have been denied since Erie Railroad v. Tompkins, 304 U.S. 64 (1938). Most state supreme courts promulgate law through their rulemaking powers and exercise various inherent powers, often devolved upon state courts from the legislature. Williams, supra p. 29, at 399. In addition to the fact that state constitutional rights provisions may differ qualitatively from the federal, other "non- rights" provisions of state constitutions may differ from the federal constitution so greatly as to profoundly change the balance of power in state government. For example, many state constitutions contain provisions enlarging judicial authority at the expense of the legislature. Also, the text of a state constitution may explicitly provide for judicial review of legislative and executive action. In fact, Williams asserts, 36 judicial review was a phenomenon of state law long before Marbury v. Madison; and contrary to the federal experience, most judiciary provisions of state constitutions have been revised and ratified in this century, often quite recently, without a serious struggle over the exercise of judicial review. Williams, supra P. 29, at 398-403. For all of the institutional and functional differences cited above and others, see Williams, supra p. 29, at 397-401, the judicial review exercised by the court in the Sheff case should be qualitatively and doctrinally different from that exercised by the federal courts. This is particularly so in an era in which the federal approach to school desegregation cases, including the state action and discriminatory intent/causation requirements, has failed overall to address so fundamental a societal problem as metropolitan-wide segregation. Viewing U. S. Supreme Court decisions as presumptively valid for state constitutional analysis, as many of the older state cases tended to do when parallel decisionmaking under provisions of both the federal and state constitutions was still the norm, denigrates the importance of state constitutional jurisprudence. Efforts to limit state decisionmaking by analytical formulations and doctrines designed to serve the purposes of the fourteenth amendment and the federal judicial system constitute an unwarranted delegation of state power to the federal courts and a resultant abdication of state judicial responsibility to provide to some of its most vulnerable citizens "the full panoply of 37 rights which Connecticut residents have come to expect as their due." Horton I, 172 Conn. at 641. 2. Connecticut courts should develop an independent approach to school desegregation cases under the Connecticut State Constitution because: a. A clear understanding of the problem to be remedied demands an effects-based jurisprudence focused on seqregative condition. Such an approach is fully supported by the express lanquage of the Connecticut Constitution and Connecticut case law. Through a series of events and doctrinal missteps described above, federal school desegregation law has moved away from the early promise of Brown I, Green, and Swann, which held the segregated condition of schools an unconstitutional deprivation of equal protection, and into a process-oriented jurisprudence which has erected a progressively more impenetrable intent/causation barrier to resolving the unique problems posed by metropolitan-wide segregation. It would be possible, of course, for the Connecticut courts to avoid the full chilling 38 . v Ee effect of this approach by carving out a narrow path through the federal jurisprudential wilderness, much as was done by some lower federal courts following Swann. This path could be constructed by adopting a doctrine of state responsibility based on the foreseeable segregative consequences of state acts. See in general Binion, supra p. 16; Goodman, supra p. 15; Liebman, supra p. 6. See also Note: School Desegregation after Swann: A Theory of Government Responsibility, 39 U. Chi. L. Rev. 421, 424- 29 (arguing that segregative intent can easily be shown in facially neutral acts such as attendance zone designation or school site location which have the natural and probable effect of fostering residential segregation and which may subsequently result in racially imbalanced schools); and Fiss, supra p. 26, at 584-85 (arguing that a deliberate choice of geographic criteria with knowledge of the probable consequences, combined with a deliberate decision not to mitigate the consequences of the prior choice reinforces the ascription of responsibility). The same result could be achieved by enlarging the categories of evidence deemed relevant in establishing intent/causation to include "root" evidence, such as community attitudes and their effect on elected officials and/or "branch" evidence, such as the decisions of other branches of state government in addition to school boards which have played a part in creating or maintaining a segregated system in both schools and housing. See Stein, supra p. 16, at 2005; Tribe, supra p. 16, at 1500 (this is also the approach taken by the federal district court in Milliken). The 39 path could also be constructed by shifting the burden of proof on intent/causation to defendants once racial isolation has been established by objective criteria, as the U. S. Supreme Court did in Swann. (The Connecticut Supreme Court took a similar burden shifting approach in Horton v. Meskill, 195 Conn. 24, 37-38 (1985) (Horton IIXI)). One might also argue that current federal doctrine encourages the approaches described above, based on the language in Columbus Board of Education v. Penick, 443 U.S. 449, 464-65 (1979) which blurred the de facto-de jure distinction by suggesting that, even in a city like Columbus which had had no statutorily mandated segregation in this century, disparate racial impact and foreseeable consequences could be "fertile ground for drawing inferences of segregative intent," even though they "do not, without more, establish a constitutional violation." Even under federal law, the argument has been made that the textual, philosophical and practical difficulties that militate against the recognition of an affirmative constitutional duty to act -- the negative constitutional language of the fourteenth amendment, the state action doctrine, and the problem of tangible standards and remedies -- do not apply, at least not as forcefully, to questions of exclusion once the state has undertaken to act. See Goodman, supra p. 15. All of these avenues could be utilized by Connecticut courts seeking a "way around" the federal standards. Constructing such a pathway under Connecticut law would, however, be a mistake. 40 All of the approaches suggested above were developed in response to federal decisions which were dictated by federal concerns and the language of the fourteenth amendment. In addition, all have been designed to conform to the so called process theory of constitutional law which holds (see supra) that courts must not intervene to remedy the conditions of segregation which have resulted from myriad government and private decisions unless this condition was "caused" by defects in the decisionmaking process itself, i.e., that the process was infected with discriminatory bias. Agreeing with Fiss that "[t]here is no independent or objective standard that can fairly ensure that race has not influenced governmental decisions," Fiss, supra p. 26, at 575 (emphasis added), we strongly suggest that the Connecticut courts reject the federal approach in full and carve out a distinctive jurisprudence based solely on the original understanding that informed Brown and all school desegregation cases prior to Keyes -- i.e., that it is the seqregative condition itself which constitutes the wrong which must be remedied. The Connecticut approach should take note of the fact that the goal of a school desegregation case is structural reform. Structural reform is premised on the notion that the quality of our social life is affected in important ways by the operation of large scale organizations. The structural suit is one in which a judge, confronting a state bureaucracy over values of constitutional dimension, undertakes to restructure the organization to eliminate the threat to those values posed by the 41 R A : : present institutional arrangement. Fiss, The Supreme Court 1978 Term: Forward: The Forms of Justice, 93 Harv. L. Rev. 1, 2 (1978). The ultimate focus of the judicial inquiry is not particularized and discrete events or acts, but rather a social condition that threatens important constitutional values and the organizational dynamic that perpetuates that condition. Id. at 18. In the structural context, Fiss continues, one function, that of the "wrongdoer", virtually disappears. The concept of "wrongdoer" presumes personal qualities: the capacity to have an intention and to choose. In a structural suit, however, the focus is not on incidents of wrongdoing but, rather, on a social condition and the bureaucratic dynamics that produced that condition. The costs and burdens of reformation are placed on the organization, not because it has "done wrong" in either a literal or metaphysical sense "for it has neither an intention nor a will," but because reform is needed to remove a threat to constitutional values posed by the operation of the organization. Id. at 22-23. A school desegregation case is a paradigmatic structural lawsuit, in which it is alleged that the segregated condition of the schools in and of itself violates the constitutional right of students attending those schools to equal protection of the laws. The remedy at issue in a structural case is the structural injunction. O. M. Fiss, supra p. 25. As opposed to preventive or reparative injunctions, the structural injunction is used to 42 effectuate the reorganization of an ongoing social institution. Id. at 7. In a structural injunction context, like a school desegregation case, it is imperative to see that "the constitutional wrong is the structure itself; the reorganization is designed to bring the structure within constitutional bounds." Id. at 11. Such an injunction does not require a judgment about wrongdoing, future or past. The structural suit and its injunctive (and/or declarative) remedy seeks to eradicate an ongoing threat to our constitutional values . . . . [I]t speaks to the future. Fiss, supra p. 41, at 23. An understanding of the need for structural reform in achieving equal educational opportunity, as well as the usefulness of the structural injunction in achieving that reform, was expressed clearly by the Connecticut Supreme Court in Horton IX11: Our own cases have similarly acknowledged that a court, in the exercise of its discretion to frame injunctive relief, must balance the competing equities of the parties to assure the relief it grants is compatible with the equities of the case, Dukes v. Durante, 192 Conn. 207, 225 (1984); and takes account of the possibility of embarrassment to the operations of government. CEUI v. CSEA, 183 Conn. 235, 248-49 (1981). Horton TIX, 195 Conn. at 47. In a school desegregation case, the courts focus must turn away from the process by which schools become segregated toward the segregated condition itself and the effects of this condition on the lives of school children, their families, and their communities. This is, in fact, the constitutional wrong to be 43 remedied, because it is the effects of racial isolation which constitute, per se, the deprivation of equal protection and equal educational opportunity which the Connecticut Constitution forbids. Many commentators agree with the structural approach advocated by Fiss under which government responsibility attaches, regardless of intent or causation, when the state fails to remedy the racial imbalance which the state has within its power to avoid. Since public school attendance is compulsory and the state and its delegated agents have complete control over attendance zones, school sites, student assignments, and all other components of a school system, not to mention the other units of state government which impact upon the problem, it is proper to hold the state accountable for harm which can be prevented. Note, supra p. 39, at 440. All governmental units are interconnected in many ways, and it would not be unreasonable to think in terms of the cumulative effect of all governmental activity and to hold particularly responsible the unit that has within its power the most effective method of correcting one facet of the cumulative impact, racially imbalanced schools. Fiss, supra p. 26, at 587. Tribe has strongly advocated such an approach, based on a new mediating principle which better comports with the underlying goal of equal protection. Tribe argues that the antidiscrimination principle, which has been used as an equal protection mediator for many years in school desegregation cases, requires a "perpetrator" who engages in the 44 invidious act of discriminating. This requirement leads inexorably to a jurisprudence based on state action, discriminatory intent and causation, and the subsequent "travesty" of Milliken. Tribe suggests that at the present stage, when the problems have become so entrenched that intent/causation is almost impossible to prove, a far better mediating principle for equal protection cases would be the antisubjugation principle, which aims not at preventing discriminatory acts, but rather at breaking down legally reinforced systems of subordination that treat some people as second class citizens. "The core value of this principle is that all people have equal worth," which comes much closer to the core value underlying the equal protection clause. L. H. Tribe, supra P. 16, at 1515. The goal of the equal protection clause is not to stamp out impure thoughts, Tribe continues, but to guarantee a full measure of dignity to all citizens. The Constitution may be offended not only by discrete acts of social discrimination, but also by governmental rules, policies, and practices that perennially reinforce the subordinate status of any group. Mediated by the antisubjugation principle, the equal protection clause asks whether the particular conditions complained of deprive a particular group of its right to be fully human. Id. at 1516. Tribe observes that the anitdiscrimination principle may be sufficient to contend with the deprivations of equal protection that result from isolated instances of overt impropriety or 45 [BJut the subjugation of blacks, women, and other groups today persisting is usually neither isolated nor hysterical. Regimes of sustained subordination generate devices, institutions, and circumstances that impose burdens or constraints on the target group without resort to repeated or individualized discriminatory actions. Id. at 1518. Tribe cites Kovel, J. Kovel, White Racism: A Psychohistory 60-66 (1971), as reminding us that the inequities that persist in American society have survived this long because they have become ingrained in our modes of thought. And as the U. S. Supreme Court recognized a century ago in Strauder v. West Yiraginia, 100 U.S. 203, 306 (1880), habitual discrimination is the hardest to eradicate. Tribe criticizes the Supreme Court's current approach to equal protection under the fourteenth amendment because the government cannot be held accountable to the constitutional norm of equality unless it has actively created a particular set of conditions at least in part "because of", not merely "in spite of", its adverse effects upon an identifiable group. (Citing Personnel Administrator v. Feeney, 422 U.S. 256 (1979). This process-oriented approach, which Tribe has criticized harshly in other writings, see Tribe, supra p. 16, at 564, overlooks the fact that minorities can be harmed when the government is only "indifferent" to their suffering, or merely blind as to how prior official discrimination contributed to it, and how current official acts or omissions will perpetuate it. L. H. Tribe, supra p. 16, at 1518-19. (Fiss has described the same phenomenon as the "policy of disregard." See Fiss, supra p. 26, at 565). Tribe argues that the pseudo-scienter requirement 46 26, at 565). Tribe argues that the pseudo-scienter requirement of Washington v. Davis, Keyes, and other cases is, therefore, utterly alien to the basic concept of equal justice under law. Whereas the antidiscrimination principle and the intent/causation requirement which it has spawned look inward to the perpetrator's state of mind, the antisubjugation principle looks outward to the victim's state of existence, L. H. Tribe, supra p. 16, at 1519, and allows the court to focus on the denial of humanity which that state imposes on certain citizens. In a school desegregation case, the anitsubjugation principle implies that by focusing on the condition of segregation existing in the schools of the nation's metropolitan ghettoes and by declaring outright that subjecting children to inherently unequal conditions constitutes a per se violation of the constitutional right to equal educational opportunity, courts can more fully realize the goal of equal protection in the constitutional framework. Such an approach may, at the present time, be beyond the reach of the federal courts; but it is fully supported, and arguably required, by the express language of Article first, § 20, of the Connecticut Constitution, which states in part that "[N]o person shall be denied the equal protection of the laws nor be subjected to segregation or discrimination in the exercise or enjoyment of his civil or political rights . . . ." Conn. Const. art. I, § 20 (emphasis added). Under the standard rules of constitutional interpretation, the word "subjected" must be construed as having some meaning and 47 meaning was clearly intended by the drafters. The ordinary meanings of "subjected", see, Random House Dictionary of the English Language 1893 (2d ed. unabridged 1987), when used as a verb and particularly when followed by "to", as it is in § 20, are: to bring under domination, control, or influence; to cause to undergo or to expose to something specified (i.e., in § 20, to segregation or discrimination); to make liable or vulnerable, lay open, or expose. Interestingly, in light of the antisubjugation principle discussed above, the word "subjugate", also a verb, is defined, id., as: to bring under complete control or "subjection"; to conquer, to master; to make submissive or subservient; to "enslave". The importance of the definitional interrelationship between the two terms, "subjugation" and "subjection", cannot be overlooked in the construction of the phrase, "be subjected to . . ." in Article first, § 20. In addition to the plain meaning rule, Connecticut courts have also ascribed to the fundamental tenet of constitutional construction which directs that a constitutional provision should be construed so as to give it effective operation and to suppress the mischief at which it was aimed, Palka v. Walker, 124 Conn. 121, 198 A. 265 (1938) (emphasis added). The insertion by the drafters of very particularized language into the second equal protection clause of the Connecticut Constitution in 1965, in full awareness of the major expansion of political and civil rights then occurring, must have been aimed at suppressing the mischief of the continued subjugation of blacks and other target 48 mischief of the continued subjugation of blacks and other target groups in Connecticut. To follow the words "subjected to" with words as uncompromisingly negative as "segregation" and "discrimination" clearly indicates that the drafters did not intend "subjected to" to carry the sunnier meaning of "to bring indies government dominion," but rather to carry the full negative burden of the phrase -- to expose, to make vulnerable -- to subjugate -- to enslave. It is reasonable to assume that the drafters recognized that, in 1965, the fact that some Connecticut citizens were still being subjected to segregation and discrimination constituted the subjugation of these citizens to second-class citizen status and could no longer be tolerated in a state committed to the equal worth of all persons under the law. The Connecticut Supreme Court expanded on this recognition in Horton I by declaring that "in Connecticut, elementary and secondary education is a fundamental right, [and] that pupils in the public schools are entitled to the equal enjoyment of that right . . . ." Horton I, 172 Conn. at 648. Reading that holding into the language of Article first, § 20, it seems clear that the Connecticut Constitution forbids subjecting any person to segregation or discrimination in the exercise or enjoyment of their fundamental right to education. Connecticut courts have also adopted the rule of construction that effect must be given to every part of and each word in the constitution unless there is a clear reason for not Qoing so, Cahill v. leobold, 141 Conn. 1, 103 A.24 3818 (1954). "discrimination", the drafters must have intended the words to carry different import. Discrimination, as noted above by Tribe, Fiss, and others, implies an invidious act by a wrongdoer. But to this constitutionally impermissible act, the drafters added a second violation -- not to segregate, which might also imply a conscious act of isolation, but rather a person's being subjected to segregation, which arguably occurs whenever a person is left to endure a segregated condition which the state might reasonably prevent. By regarding state-imposed school district lines as sacrosanct and refusing to abridge them; by valuing a child's fundamental right to an equal education less highly than a town's interest in maintaining impermeable borders, which can of course be readily breached to achieve cost savings in police and fire protection or garbage removal, the state has knowingly subjected these children to segregation and to its known harmful effects, and has consented to their continued subjugation as second-class citizens in the majority culture. Many states have adopted the per se approach to government responsibility advocated here, based on the premise that racially unbalanced schools are inherently unequal and that the failure of the state to remedy this unequal treatment of minorities is a denial of equal protection regardless of the underlying causes. On this reasoning, intent and/or foreseeability are irrelevant. In People v. San Diego Unified School District, 19 Cal. App. 3d 252, 96 Cal. Rptr. 658 (4th Dist. Ct. App. 1971), cert. denied 92 S. Ct. 1288 (1972), the California State Court of Appeals, 50 S. Ct. 1288 (1972), the California State Court of Appeals, reversing the trial court, found that the knowing failure of the school board to remedy the imbalance, when it was shown to have resulted in inferior education for black students, was sufficient to attribute responsibility for curing the problem to the state. While recognizing that the presumption of educational inequality was rebuttable and that practical limits might make complete integration impossible, the court ultimately adopted an approach that would require a finding of government responsibility in most . if not all cases of racially imbalanced schools. Note, supra p. 39, at 430. A similar approach was taken by the New Jersey Supreme Court in Jenkins v. Township of Morris School District, 58 N.J. 483, 469 (1971). Recommending an. interdistrict remedy to solve racial imbalance, that court eschewed the seemingly inviolate nature of school district lines, saying "governmental subdivisions of the state may readily be abridged when necessary to vindicate state constitutional rights and policies." The holdings in Horton I-III and the principle of "basic fairness" which the Connecticut Supreme Court announced as underlying all equal protection cases under the Connecticut Constitution in Moscone v. Manson, 440 A.2d 848 (1981), militates in favor of this approach in Connecticut, particularly in light of the clear and convincing evidence which we now possess and of which the state is fully aware (see discussion infra) in re: the severe social, academic, and intellectual detriments suffered by children in segregated schools as opposed to those in racially 51 The state's own experts originally recommended just such a per se approach to the segregative conditions in the Hartford area schools, as well as in other metropolitan areas throughout Connecticut, calling for "collective responsibility" among the cities and their contiguous and adjacent suburbs in eradicating racial imbalance in the schools. See A Report on Racial/Ethnic Equity and Desegregation in Connecticut's Public Schools, Prepared for Presentation to the Connecticut State Board of Education by The Committee on Racial Equity, Appointed by the Commissioner of Eduction, Conn. St. Bd. of Educ., at 11-18 (Jan. 1988). The state's knowing failure to eradicate the condition of metropolitan-wide segregation currently existing in Connecticut is all the more intolerable because of the state's power, through both its acts and omissions, to "define expectations, confer legitimacy, establish a status quo, and thus necessarily shape the nature and distribution of interests and attitudes in society itself." Tribe, supra p. 16, at 1078. By refusing to resolve the problem, the state affirms this aspect of the status quo, racial imbalance in metropolitan-area schools and its effects, as inevitable. Surely this is a constitutionally impermissible result. b. A per se approach to seqregative condition under the Connecticut Constitution is supported by empirical research studies which unequivocally 52 affirm the value of racially balanced schools to minority and white students alike, to their parents, and to the society at large. Deprivation of an opportunity to attend such schools in metropolitan areas such as Hartford and its surrounding suburbs is a per se denial of the fundamental right to equal educational opportunity, mandated by Horton I. "In the short run, it may seem to be the easier course to allow our great metropolitan areas to be divided up each into two cities -- one white, the other black -- but it is a course, I predict, our people will ultimately regret." Justice Thurgood Marshall, dissenting in Milliken v. Bradley, 418 U.S. at 814. It seems especially fitting at the time of Justice Marshall's retirement from the Supreme Court to recall these words from Milliken and to use them as a starting point for assessing the results of school desegregation plans in the nation's cities. There is a bittersweet irony in this assessment. James Liebman has answered the question, "Is school desegregation dead?" by observing that school desegregation appears to be "alive and well" throughout the South in cities like Charlotte-Mecklenburg, Greenville, Jacksonville, Louisville, Nashville-Davidson, and Tampa-St. Petersburg, as well as in cities in the North such as Buffalo, Columbus, Dayton, Denver, Minneapolis, St. Louis, San Diego, and Wilmington-New Castle 53 where mandatory school desegregation plans were initiated. Liebman, supra p. 6, at 1463, 1465-67 and nn. 6 & 7. To this exemplary list must be added Stamford, Connecticut, which alone among Connecticut's cities has succeeded in effectively integrating its schools, also under a mandatory school desegregation plan. The most authoritative current research has established the fact that tremendous progress has been achieved in areas with court or administratively-ordered desegregation plans, whereas little or no progress has been noted in 85% of districts without such plans. Id. at 1467-69, citing F. Welch and A. Light, New Evidence on School Desegregation, 40, 67, and Table 12 (U.S. Commission on Civil Rights, Clearinghouse Publ. 92 1987). The same research has shown that the highest level of progress has been achieved in areas in which the desegregation plan was mandatory rather than voluntary and where the plan included interdistrict desegregation techniques such as pairing and clustering. Countywide plans were particularly effective. The irony, of course, is that many such plans were implemented in the South which, as a region, has demonstrated more progress in integration than any other in the country. ld. at 6, Tables 1, Al, and A2. In the generation since these executive branch and court-ordered desegregation plans were initiated, widespread progress has been substantiated through empirical research, progress which could only be predicted in 1954. Writing in 1965, 54 progress which could only be predicted in 1954. Writing in 1965, Fiss catalogued the various harms which were then said to result from segregation: the psychological harm to black children, who feel insult and stigma whether their schools have been de jure or de facto segregated; the academic and intellectual harms resulting from inferior school plants, educational materials, teachers, and curriculums; and the perpetuation of social barriers which results from minority children being "deprived of one further opportunity to develop relationships with members of. the dominant class." Fiss, supra p. 26, at 568-570. Fiss acknowledged the difficulty in drawing causal connections in the absence of empirical data showing that such harms can be remedied by attacking the segregated condition itself, but argued that support for this proposition "is suggested by the embryonic indications of improved . . . achievement by [minority students] in integrated schools." Id. at 568. The indications are no longer embryonic. Research data now unequivocally shows that minority performance in desegregated schools has improved. See M. Weinberg, The Search for Quality Integrated Education 146-76 (1983) (reviewing literature); Taylor & Brown, Equal Protection and the Isolation of the Poor, 95 Yale L.J. 1700, 1700-11, nn. 36-42 (1986). Minorities' performance on standardized achievement tests have risen in desegregated settings. Mahard & Crain, Research on Minority Achievement in Deseqgregated Schools, in The Consequences of School Deseqregation 124 (C. Rossell & W. Hawley eds. 1983). It is well documented 55 schools have improved. T. Cook, Black Achievement and School Desegregation 985 (1984) (finding that black students educated in desegregated schools are more likely to graduate from high school and college and to major in more remunerative subjects). Liebman has also cited research, see, supra p. 6, at 1624, n.675, indicating that in addition to improvements in standardized test scores and career options, minority students have made substantial gains in I.Q. scores which erase a third to one half of the overall difference between black and white students. These gains, widely believed to be due to the changing expectations of black students by teachers in deseqgreqgated settings, are strongest when deseqregation begins in the early grades, has a metropolitan-wide plan, and takes place in predominately white schools with a critical mass of black students. Braddock & McPartland, The Social and Academic Consequences of School Desegregation, Equity & Choice, Feb. 1988, at 6. Moreover, "the preponderance of empirical evidence suggests that [desegregated] schools can contribute to reducing the social stigma of being black . . . [and also] make both black and white students more comfortable in racially integrated settings." Liebman, supra p. 6, at 1630 citing sources noted at n. 696. None of this progress has been achieved, as had been feared in 1954, at the expense of white Students’ progress, nor has racial animosity or "white flight", which may occur at the beginning stages of a given implementation plan, been the 56 ee » beginning stages of a given implementation plan, been the permanent result. Id. at 1621-1630 and particularly nn. 664-693. See also F. Welch and A. Light, supra p. 54, at 3-4. These results have been further documented by the State of Connecticut's own experts, relying inter alia upon the Mahard and Crain study cited above as well as their own commissioned study by J.W. Schofield, Review of School Desegregation's Impact on Elementary and Secondary School Students, State of Connecticut, Board of Education (1989). It should also be noted that this solid empirical record of progress has not been matched by any of the alternative approaches to providing equal educational opportunity in racially isolated settings, such as "separate but enhanced schools" (termed the "gilded ghetto" approach by Liebman and others), "effective schools", school-based management methodologies, all- minority high schools, minority control of city school boards and other political institutions, and decentralized school districts. Liebman, supra p. 6, at 1489 n. 142. This failure by minority students to achieve equal educational and social progress in segregated as opposed to integrated school settings, i.e., under plans which focus on "equal treatment and equal access" or other "make-do in segregated schools" methodologies, has also been noted by the Governor's Commission on Quality and Integrated Education, the state's second group of experts which has stressed the vital importance of racially balanced school settings to the school achievement and to the social adjustment of minority 57 3 $ ACL Equity and Excellence: A Vision of Ouality and Integrated Education for Connecticut, The Report of The Governor's Commission on Quality and Integrated Education (December 1990.) Perhaps if the research data were not so conclusive, it would still be possible to argue that the state can provide equal educational opportunity in the public schools in ways other than assuring integrated school settings to all Connecticut public school students. But the evidence is now in, and it is overwhelming. In Brown I, the U. S. Supreme Court declared that segregated schools are inherently unequal, largely on the basis of tentative sociological data which appeared to point in that direction. There is now irrefutable proof that this statement was correct. Separate but equal can never be equal. To deprive students, their parents, and their communities of the documented social, intellectual, academic, and career achievements possible in integrated schools is a per se deprivation of the fundamental right to equal educational opportunity mandated in Horton I because we now know, and the state well knows, that a like opportunity cannot be provided in any other way. Like the minority children in the Detroit public schools, which both the federal district court and the U. S. Supreme Court recognized as impervious to racial balancing without an interdistrict plan, minority children in the Hartford schools are unable to obtain an equal educational opportunity because their schools are now attended by a school population of which over 90% are members of minority groups. These students, as well as 58 * nonminority students in both city and suburban schools, are also deprived of a racially-balanced school setting which is mandated for all students under Connecticut school law. By adopting a constitutional interpretation which says, as the Supreme Court in effect said in Milliken, "We know that Hartford-area school children are being deprived of an equal educational opportunity due to their forced attendance in racially unbalanced schools within state-authorized attendance zones -- but unless affirmative discriminatory acts of state officials can be shown to have caused the problem, the state has no duty to correct it," the court will be perpetuating the serious error made at the federal level which has made metropolitan-wide segregation all but impossible to remedy in the federal courts. The court will also be reducing the affirmative duty of the state to provide for equal educational opportunity in racially balanced schools by appropriate legislation to meaningless rhetoric. Instead, the court should build on the excellent foundation laid by Horton I-III, perhaps taking the lead from other states such as Montana where in Helena Elementary School District v. State, 769 P.2d 684 (Mont. 1989), the Montana Supreme Court declared a fundamental right to education and held that the state constitutional guarantee of equality of educational opportunity was not merely an aspirational goal but a real guarantee, binding on all three branches of government, whether at the state, local, or school district level. Id. at 684-688. Surely, in light of what we now know can be achieved by 59 * making good on such a guarantee, Horton requires no less.