Attorney Notes
Working File
January 1, 1981

Cite this item
-
Case Files, Thornburg v. Gingles Working Files - Guinier. Current Issues in Reapportionment (Law and Policy Quarterly), 1981. 2cae30d2-db92-ee11-be37-6045bdeb8873. LDF Archives, Thurgood Marshall Institute. https://ldfrecollection.org/archives/archives-search/archives-item/149056e6-07d8-41a5-acd4-73a2c2471d16/current-issues-in-reapportionment-law-and-policy-quarterly. Accessed April 06, 2025.
Copied!
IIf rD l()LICf, QUAEIEnII (1982 lorthoclag) CONSE*T I85OE8 D NBTPEOBEIOT{EtT' Bernard Grofman School of Soclal Sclences ini*"sity of Callfornla' IrYlne Howard Scirrow iieoirtment of Polltlcal Sclence ;i:i! fii;.ilii'oi ttu Yok rt Stonv Erook tteccnben 22' l98t t Thls research ras supported by tlSF Grants ,sw 77-24479 and SES ,80-07915. The authors would llke to acknowledge thelr lndebtedness to ' the partlclpants ln the Conference on Representatlon and Apportlomentr San Dlego, June 11-15, 1980 (cosponsored by the National Sclence Foundatlon and the Anerlcan Bar Assoclatlon), for helpful discusslon of many of the lssues consldered ln thls paper. l{e a'lso have dram freely upon the lnvaluable revla of court cases published by the tlational ConferenCe of State Leglslatures, Reapportlorunent, Lav and Technology (edtted by.Andrer J. ttollock) and upoo our ont Drevlors rrk' It I. II. lIl. . TAstE tr CotlTtllTs Introductlon Crlterla for Slngle-l{ember Dlstrtctlng 1. Conpetlng 0lstrlcttng Crlterla 2. Proportlonaltty of Group Representatlon and Afflrnrtlve Actlon GerrYmanderlng l 3. The Balloon Effect a. Cholce of Dlstrlctlng ilechanlsm itectton t4echanlsms 0ther than Stngte-lrlenber Dlstrlcts rlth Plrrl ltY-8ased El ectlons 1. llultlsrember and At'large Plurallty-Based Electlons 2, tlelghted Votlng, Approval Votlng' the Alternatlve Yota' rnd Proportloral Representatlon Comluslons L lntroductlon In Baker v. Carr (369 U.S. 186 (1962)) the U.S. Supreme Court afflrmed that Judlclal redress could be sought to conpel a state to reapportlon lts leglslature ln accord wlth new census data. In a nurnbcr of subsequent cases, the Court addressed ltself to the lssue of voter representatlon and the constltutlonal acceptablllty of varlous apportlorment and votlng schemes. ilost of those cases lnvolved an expllcatlon of the meanlng of the l4th lmendment .equal protecHon. clause as lt applled to Congresslonal, state, and Iocal apportiorment lssur,es. The notlon of 'equal protection' suggests various criterla rtrlch re might rlrh anY electoral scheme to satlsfy. At minlmum, of cours€, rg would wlsh to guarantee each cltlzen the rlght to exerclse hls vote. However, once re moye beyond thls baslc rlght, the quesHon of xhat 'equal protectlonr requlres (or rather, dlsrllors) becomes a very dlfflcult one. In llesber.ry v. Sanders (376 U.S. I (1964)), a case rrtrlch struck dom as unconstltuilonal gross populatlon dlsparltles among Georgia Congresslonal dlstrlcts, the U.S. Supreme Court (376 U.S. at 8) held that '(0)ne man's vote . . . ls to be worti . . . as much as anotherrs.' tri Reynolds-v. Slms (3.77 U.S. 533 (1964)) and lts companlon cases, the court extended thls 'one personr one vote' doctrlne to state leglslatures holdlng, ln dlfferent hrt equlvalent language (377 U.S. at 568), that r(A)n lndlvldualrs rlght to vote for state leglslators ls unconstltutlonally.lnpatred *ren lts relght ls ln a substantlal fashloo lY. f .'.. 2 dtiuted when ccmpared rlth votes of cltlzens llvlng ln other parts of the state.' In Avery v. l,lldland Cornty (390 U.S. 474 (1968)) the Court extended the scope of lts rullngs dom to the loctl level for, unlts wlth ipneral responslblllty.' All these cases lnvolved plurallty electlons rlth slngle-member dlstrlcts ln whlch there were large dlfferences ln the dlstrict populatlons. In these cases' the Colrt asserted that each lndlvldual who votes should have hls vote count'equallf wlth the vote cast by each other lndlvldual, 1.e., glrcn'one person, one vote're vlsh rone vote, one value' (Auerbach, 1964). The dlfflculty cann ln operatlonallzlng such a crlterlon. In Reynolds v. Slms the Court asserted that the 'equal protectlon' clause of the U.S. Constltutlon dld not requlre preclse numerlcal equallty but'honest and good falth effort to construct distrlcts . . .. as nearly of equal populatlon as ls practlcable." The Reynolds declslon also acknowledged the posslblllty of conslderations other than strlct populatlon equallty enterlng lnto apportlorment declslons. So long as the dl,rergences fron a strict populatlon standard ar'e based on legltlmate conslderatlons lncldent to the effectuatlon of a ratlonal state policy, some devlatlons frsn the equal populatlon prlnclple are constltutlonally permlsslble (377 U.S. at 579). However, rtrlle Reynolds ldentlfied r-".".., where states mlght rlsh to act, e.9., rto malntaln the lntegrlty of varlous polltlcal subdlvlslons' lnsofar as posslble, and provlde for conpact dlstrlcts of contlguous terrltorjl (377 U.S. rt 578), the Court ras rqulck to llnlt the range of rcccptrblc Justlflcrtlons for deulatlons fro the equal popul.tlon rule' 3 (Trlbe, 19782746-7471, In subsequent declslons the Court has reiterated the need for very strlct populatlon equallty ln Congresslonal dlstrlctlng --declslons (see esp. Klrkpatrick v. Prelsler (1969) 394 U.S. 526, rhere the Court reJected as unconstitutlonal a dlstrictlng wlth an average devlatlon of .745 percent frqn strlct equality. In that case' the largest district exceeded the ldeal of perfect dlstrlct population equallty by 2.43 percent; the smallest distrlct was below the ldeal by ' 1.7 percent for a nrange" of 4.13 percent). The Court, however, has allowed for greater flexibl'lity ln state dlstrlctlng declslons and even gneater flexlblllty ln local dlstrlctlng declsions. (See esp. I'lahan v. Howell 410 U.S..315 (1973), and Abate v. Mundt 403 U.S. 182 (1971). where ranges of 15.4 percent and 11.9 percent, respectively' were pennitted). Uhen the Supreme Court entered the reapportionment 'thicket' ln Baker y. carr, (369 U.S. 186 at 3OO (1951)), Justlce Frankfurter warned that r,l.lhat ls actually asked of the Court ln thls case lS to choose among conpefi ng bases of representatlon--ultlmately, real ly among competlng bases of representatlon.n Looking back on that warning' rlth the benefit of over 15 years of htndsight, we can see that, while the road frm Baker v. Carr (ln which a state legis'lature was merely requlred to fulflll lts own constitutional requlrement for perlodlc reapportionment) to the . strlct equal populatlon guide llnes of Kirkpatrlck v. Preisler (394 U.S. 526 (1969)) was not a stralght one, the Court's task along the xay uas alded lrmeasurably by the exlstence of clear statlstlcrl measures through whlch the amount of devlatlon frqn Populatlon equallty ln dlfferent leglslatures (or the srme leglslature at dlfferent perlods) could be .T rt cmpared. These statlstlcal measures (e.g., standard devlailon, average devlatlon, electoral percentage; see especlally the adrnlrable dlscusslon ln l{ollock, 1980: 5-9) allowed the court to set out clear g,itdeilnes as to rtat level of devlatlon fron strlct populailon equallty would be allowed for each type of govermentar unlt (federal, state, and local), The prlnclpal focus of most reapporfiorment cases ln the 60rs through the mld 70's was ln specrfyrng standards for popuratron equalrty of dlstrlcts and mathematlcal formulae to assess compllance wlth these standards. (see lrollock, 1980:5-20, or Trrbe, 197g, for further detalls of these cases.) uhlle the corrt maJorlty ln lts hlstoric deciston ln Reynolds asserted that the goal of the court was the achlevement of,falr and effectlre representaHonr' ln fact, however, most of the court.s energles ln the apportlorment area until the mld 70's were devoted to the elucldatlon of the standards of populailon equallty across distrrcts rhlch would govern ln each type of goverrunental Jurlsdlcilon. However, by def lnlng equallty of crilzen representailon rn terms of equally populated dlstrlcts, the supreme court was able to avold ln most of the early reapportiorment cases, ever really comlng to gnlps wlth the deeper lssues of the phl'losophy of representatlon. In many of the key apportlorment cases (e.g. llesberry v. sanders 376 u.s. at 1g; Reynolds v. slm 377 u.s. at 559-580), the court's termrnology, lf not rts reasonlng, ls sloppy ln clarmrng equal representaHon for egual numbers of peop.le as Its goal; and then equafing ,equal popu't ailoni rlth 'equal represcntatlon.,l (See Dlxon, 19692 ZZI-ZZil!. Only a lttila rcflectloo ls rcqrlrcd to see the very seyere llnltailons of deflnlng equallty of cltlzen representatlon solely ln terms of equally populated dlstrlcts. As Dlxon 11969:zztl qulte strongly (ano rue bellevc qultc rccurately) put lt: (T)here is no such thing as 'equal representation' in adlstrict system of e'lecting legislatois. There may be ,equal populatlonr districts, which ls an obJecilve'ly verifiable' concept. But with a district basls there can-never be ,equal representatlon' because all dlstrlcHng discriminates by dlscountlng utterly the votes of the minorlty voters. Let us envlsage two cltlzens: one llves ln a hlghly compeiltlrre dlstrlct, where every vote counts--so to speak--and another lives in a distrlct whlch always goes for the same party each year by a 4 to I or 5 to 1 margln.' One cltlzen alwqys has a chance to determine his distrlct.s electoral outcome; the other neve" has.2 It ls far frtrn obvlous that these two cltlzens are equally well represented. Indeed, one of the mst dlstlngulshed scholars ln the reapportlorment area, the late Robert Dlxon, argued that A goal of 'equal representaHon' can be approximated only through.abolishlng single member dlstricts and using proportional representation, such as the party llst-form used ln Europe, gr sme verslon of the Hare system . . ., (E)qual representatlon' ls generically a proportional representaHon concept. (Dlxon, 1959:228) In the 1960s the prlnclple was clearly establlshed that courts could lntervene ln the politlcal process to protect cltlzen rights to effectlvc representatlon defined ln tems of equally populated and periodically reapportloned dlstrlcts. It ls hard, ln retrospect, to appreclate hor' tireatenlng thls court lnvolvement ln the reapportlonnent process was T 6 then seen to be. l{hat ras controverslal then ls taken for granted now, and the doctrlne of 'one person, one voter has been elevated to the status of moral platltude. In the 1970s the supreme court was forced to begln to confront the subtler and far more ccnplex lssues of rfalr and effecfive representatlon' ln terms of the constltutlonallty of electlon mechanlsms other than slngle member dlstricfinq and, for equlpopulous slngle member distrlctlng, ln tenns of determln{ng when the drawlng of dlstrlct llnes constltutes unconstltuilonal raclal or parilsan gerrymanderlng. In Sectlons II and III of thls paper we shall dlscuss these two rssues, (l) electlon mechanlsms other than slngle-member distrrcts and (2) rsophlstlcatedr gerrymanderlng; ln greater detall; slnce they rlll be the representatlon quesfions rlth rtrlch the key court cases of the l9g0s.can be erpected to deal. Because malapporfionment of state leglslatures was for many lears the subJect of crltlcal corment by polrilcal.screnilsts, rt was to be expected that once court-ordered reapporilonment occurred, analysts rould. set about trying to measure lts lmpact. Glven the methodorogrcal dlfflcultles rtrlch beset most early studles of reapporilorment lmpact, and the vlrtual absence of any later more methodlcally soph{stlcated studles' the guestlon of the pollilcal lmpact of reapporilonment ls, horever, llttlc better understoodtodqy thrn lt ras ten yearc ago. (sec Srffcll. 1982 forthcotng) II. Crlterla for Slngle l{enber 0lstrlctlng 1. ConfllctinS Crlteria lle lnventory ln Table I nearly two dozen crlterla for evaluating the falrness of apporilorment schemes. Impectlon of thls table makes lt apparent that there are multlple and confllctlng 'reasonab]e' goals *tlch have been advocated for reapportlorment declslon-maklng. Moreover, th63e Crlterla are not JuSt lnventlons of academlC researchers rith time on thelr hands--a Iarge nunber of them have been enshrined lnto statute. Indeed, reformers of the ccmmon cause mode, anxlous to keep'politlcs' out of the reapportlorynent arena ln the 1980's, have advocated tying the hands of those dolng the reapportioning by saddling these.decision-makers wlth an extenslve lnventory of statutorlly mandated crlterla for 'falr' dlstrlcHng. In prlnclple, the ldea ls to put so many constralnts on thc process that there's only one plan (or at most a handful of plars) that satlsfles the enumerated crlterla, and to plck the set of'crlterla So thtt there's no mblgulty about how they're meant to apply'3 Table I about here Thls seanlngly reasonable ldea falls at three cruclal polnts.. Flrst' enough of the proposed crlterla for slngle-nember dlstrlctlng (e.9.' CgtpactneSS, av6ldange Of breakup Of 'natural Comunltlesr' avoldance Of dllutlon of the votlng strength of raclal or llngulstlc orlnorltles) 1rc. ln fact left so l,ll-deflned as to stlll lcave open t 893! der'l of 8 flexlblllty. Indeed, ln most cases there would at mlnlmum be hundredS of plans that arguably satlsfy all the speclfled gutdellnes' Second, many of the proposed crlteria are lnccmpatlble lrt who'le or ln part, and the courts are golng to face ln the 1980's the task of untangllng rhat varlors sets of crlterla 'really' mean and how reapportlorment statutes shall be lnterpreted when statutory provlslons tnclude confllctlng crlterla. For example, to provlde certaln geographlcally dlspersed mlnorltles wlth dlstrlcts ln whlch 'thelrr Yolce rlll not be submerged may requlre crosslng of county/clty boundarles and/or requlre vlolatlons of mlnlmal dlstrlct compactness. All three of these requlrements--lntegrlty of political boundarles, conpactness, and mlnorlty representatlon--are to be found in callfornla's State Constltutlon, recently amended by voter referendum (Proposltlon 5, June 1980), and slml.lar constltutional or statutory provlslons exlst ln at least a dozen other states (e.g', Colorado)' Although the Callfornla anendment llStS crlterla ln order of lmportance, lt ls far frcrn clear frm the language of that amendment that the llstlng is lntended to provlde a lexlcographlc orderlng. ln caltfornla (and elsewhere) we would' rntlctpatesultsalleglngthatalternatlvedlstrlctlngplanscould pnovlde large lmprovements ln certaln crlterla (e'9', mlnorlty representatlon) wlth only mlnlmal cost to other crlterla (e'9.' ccmpactness) and thus should be pneferred Thlrd, ln focusslng on formal crlterla (e'g', cqnpactness)' most lf not rll of ttre recently proposed (or enacted) sets of crlterla dlsregard thc 'polltlcrl' consequences of redlstrlctlng 's neasured by the 9 relatlonshlp between a polltlcal party's vote share and lts expected sert share. As the late Robert Dixon clearly polnted out (Dixon, 1981, forthcomlng), lhere are several key facts ln dlstrlctlng whlch must be understood. One fact ls that there ls not Just one but hundreds of uays that a ccmputer can draw dlstrict llnes rtrlch wlll satlsfy the court's lns!stence on populatlon equallty. (See esp. Backstrm et al., 1978.) A second key fact {s that there are no *neutral' cholces among thls great varlety of optlons. *llhether the llnes are drawn by a nlnth-grade clvlcs class, a board of Ph.D.ts, or a cmputer, every llne on a map aligns partlsans and lnterest blocs ln a partlcular way,'and election results wlll vary accordlng to whlch llnes are chosen. A thlrd key fact, whlch Dlxon lanented, ls that'the flrst two facts are not understood by the Judges who rule on these (reapportlonment) matters, by many Journallsts who report on these matters, and by members of the general publlc" I,lhat Dixon argued for (1982 forthcoming) ls that we should avold r dlstrlctlng process wlrlch can be characterlzed by either one of tvo extremes--the extpeme of partisan lust (to use an apt phrase due to tr,layhew,1971) or the extreme of legislative maps drawn by blindfolded grtographers. Rather, we should see the dlstrlctlng process as one ln whlch we try to reallze certaln artlculated values, recognlzlng that smlg of these values are mutua'lly lnconpatlble ln utrole or in part and that trade-offs are requlred. In our vlew, whlle 'partlsan lust' ls clearly lmpermlsslble, consclous conslderatlon of the probable partisan (and also raclal/I lngulstlc) lmpll catlons of alternrtl ve dlstrl ctlng schemr ls deslrable. 0f course, drarlng the llne betreen pernlsslble and s l0 impermlsslble ipolltlcal' conslderatlons ln the dlstrlctlng process ls not easy. 8ut ne should note that the Supreme Court has clearly lndlcated that taklng lnto account the expected.partlsan lmpact of a dlstrlctlng scheme as one of the factors ln chooslng anong alternatlve schemes ls not prohlblted (see our dlscusslon of Gaffney v. Cumnlngs belor); and lndeed, ln the case of lmpact on raclal/lingulstlc representatlon such foreslght as to expected consequences may even be held to be necessary for Jurlsdlctlons covered by the Votlng Rlghts Act (see dlscusslon of raclal vote dilutlon standards belm). tlhat are the va'lues vrtrlch should be taken lnto account ln dlstrlctlng? tlo doubt most famlllar ls the goal of preservlng 'natural' csnnr,nltles and the related goal of not crosslng polltlcal subunlt boundarles. 0ther rell-known goals lnc'lude requlring contlgulty of dlstrlcts and lmposlng a requ{rement of dlstrlct compactness. lut there are certaln other valuesr not generally as famlllar, wtrlch are also rorthy of reallzatlon and 91trlch mlght ln.certaln lnstances appear mone ccmpelllng than the ones Just mentloned (see Table 1): (l) The maJorlty rule prlnclple: l{hlle the Supreme Court has perslstently refused to endorse any crlterlon of strlct proportlonal representatlon, at mlnlmm lt mtght be argued that votlng maJorltles shorld be transfonned lnto leglslatlve maJorltles and that any dlstrlctlng whlch falled to achleve thls had falled to provlde falr and cffectlve representatlm (see Scarror, 1982, forthcornlng). The Supreme Canrt has, horever, not jet been confronted Ylth such an argument' or rltlr docunentrtlon rtrlch rould demonttrrta that a glven dlstrlctlng ll effort uas so biased as to consistently be llkely to deny a group rlth the support of a maJorlty of voters control of the legislaturet rnd thus deny effectlve,implementatlon of the maJority rule prlnclple. (2) Absence of blas: At the aggregate level, for partisan elections, an even more general goal than that of translating an electoral maJorlty lnto a leglslatlve maJorlty ls the goal that the dlstrlcting systern not be biased agalnst one or the other of our two maJor partles. Thls crlterion has been termed 'neutralltyr by l{ieml and Deegan (1978). 8y neutrallty we mean that both partles should have to poll approxlmately the same proportion of the vote ln order to wln a glven portlon.of the dlstrlcts. (t{ote that the maJorlty rule princlple ls subsumed ln the prlnclple of neutrallty. Any two-party.statem xtrlch satlsfles neutrallty wlll (un'less lt ls perverse) necessarily glve a votlng maJority at least a bare maJorlty of leglslatlve seats.) tlhy should one party have to poll 55 percent of the state vote ln order to wln a maJority of the leglslature, whlle the other party has to poll only, say, 48 percent? I'lhy should a party be denied maJority control of the legls'lature lf lt polls a maJority of the vote? Any one' or any group, whlch deslgns a dlstrlctlng system rrtrlch achleves these results--even lf the system ls the product of well-lntentloned, : bllndfolded nonpartlsans--has deslgned a system whlch has achleved thc very opposlte of falr and effectlve representatlon. (3) Preservatlon of mlnlmal representatlon: In addltlon to belng neutral (unbalsed), lt seerns rersonable that a dlstrlctlng systen should 15surc that nelther pafty ls ever totally obllterated by a landsllde. To assure that result, as nell as to lnsure sane contlnulty of leglslatlve mnbershlp, there must be ssne safe dlstrlcts for each party. (4) Polltlcat ccmpetltlveness: 0n the other hand, however, lt also app€ars deslrable that many dlstrlcts should be competltlve. Hor else ls nar blood golng to be lnfused lnto the leglslature, or hor else ls maJorlty control golng to shlft back and forth as the maJorlty sentlment ln the electorate shlfts back and forth? The problein, of course, ls how these varlous crlterla can be reconclled. t{leml and Deegan (1978), ln what ls destlned to be a classlc essayr have begun to speclfy feasible trade-offs between goals such as electoral responslvenets, neutrality, and conpetltlveness. In deslgnlng dlstrlctlng plans, we belleve that the trade-off issue can be addressed ln an operrtlons research framework as a problem of maxlmlzlng a speclfled obJectlve functlon (a relghted set of goals) subJect to constralnts (the votlng strength of the relevant partles/groups ln the electorate and the geographlc dlstrlbutlon of thls votlng strength). As far as.He are aware, the only dlrect appllcatlons of the powerful mathematlcal tools ln the operatlon research llterature to the polltlcal aspects of reapportlonment are Nleml and Deegan (1978) and l,lusgrove (1977), although operatlons research technlques have often been used to flnd sets of dlstrlcts whose devlatlons from an equal populatlon standard frll rlthln an acceptable range and many avallable programs also take' dlstrlct corpactness lnto account. (See e.9., Nagel , 1972.1 lle belleve rork on fonnal characterlstlcs of the trade-off relatlonshlgs eong confllct{ng crlterlr fon rfalr and effectlve' t3 representatlon can be useful ln clarifylng (a'lbelt certainly not resolving) the value choices faced by those engaged in redistrlctlng by provldlng lnvaluable lnsight lnto what cholces are lgg{!lg. Sfinllerly, such research could ultlmately be of great value to the courts. 2. Proportionality of Group Representatlon and Afflrmatlve Action Gerymanderi ng If we look to the aggregate outcome level, one natural crlterlon to Judge apportlorment schemes by ls proportlonal representation of group lnterests: the crlterion that cognlzable groups (whether political parties or rqclal or rellglous mlnorltles) obtaln representatlon ln the leglslature proportlonal to thelr share of population.4 In l,lhltcomb (403 U.S. at 153-154), the U.S. Supreme Court expllcltly reJected the vlew that the protectlon of mlnorlty rlghts requires sqrn form of proportlonal representatlon for mlnorlties. The Court in Ihitccmb, like the Federal Dlstrlct Court before lt, eschewed any lndlcatlon that Negroes llving in the ghetto were entltled to any certaln number of leglslators. Rather, "dlstrlcts should be dram with an e1t that ls color bllnd, and sophlstlcated gerrymanderlng would not be countenanced" (llhitcsnb, 403 U.S. at 138, cf. 305 F. Supp at l39l-92). Nonetheless, ln a serles of cases beginnlng wlth Gaffney v. Ctrnrnings (412 U.S. 735 (f973)), the U.S. Suprerne Court has cqne remarkably close to endorslng dlstrlctlng deslEred to lnsure proportional representatlon of groups when thls apportloment does not vlolate equal populltlon strndards. In Gaifney the Court uas confronted vlth a scheme deslged to 12 l4 guarantee each party a percentage of House and Senate seats ln the connectlcut leglslature proportlonal to thelr share of the statewlde vote. To do thls the clear maJorlty of seats was designed to be ,safe, for one or the other party. The result ras descrlbed by proponents rs ra falr polltlcal balancer. and by opponents as rpolltlcal gerrymanderlng.. The Supreme Cort, acceptlng tn effect the former characterlzafion, aiserted that (tt)eittrer we nor the district courts have a constitutlona'lyarrant to lnvalldate a state plan, otherwise withln to'lerable ploportion limits, because lt undertakes, not to minimlze or eliminate the political strength of 6ny lroup or party, but to recognlze lt and, through dlstrlctlng, provlde a rough sort of proportlonal. representailon ln the leglslatlve halls-of thestate (412 U.S. at 754). Accordlng to Gerhard casper (1973:23), rThe court had never before gone so far ln supportlng proporHonal representafion as an ldeal.r Horever, as one lawler (Dolgow, Lgll:4l}) has polnted out, lf a leglslature can establlsh distrlct llnes to falrly represent the tro donlnant polltlcal lnterests, lt ls not dlfflcult to lmaglne lts proceeding one'step further and 'locklng' those lnterests lnto the cltadels of power. There are several lmportant phllosophlcal and pollcy lssues ralsed by the Gaffney declslon re 'sophlsficated' polltical gerrymanderlng. One of these ls the deslrablllty of rsafe-seat' dlstrlctlng. Another lssue lrlses, lf lnstead of Denocrats and Repub'llcans, ye are deallng rlth other groupsr e.9,, raclal, rcllglous, or llngulst{c mlnorltlca, }lor 3hflld thrt rffrct our Judgmont u to tlre rpproprlrtcness of l5 gerrymanderlng ln the lnterest of guaranteed mlnorlty representatlon? Consider two groups roughly equal ln slze occupylng a territory whlch ls to be partiHoned lnto tuo dlstrlct!. Should thls partltloning be done so as to gl,n each group one safe seat? 0r would lt be preferable to foster polltlcal ccmpetitlon and fluldity--ln which candidates might rlsh to seek support across partlsan/raclal/religious lines? Uhat if the ratlo ls 60/40? Should the mlnority stlll get a safe seat? Slnllarly' conslder a mlnorlty uhlch makes up roughly one thlrd of the populatlon of an area (over whlch lt ls spread falrly evenly) whlch ls to be partltloned lnto three districts. Shou'ld the strength of this minority be concentrated so as to vlrtually guarantee lt one seat' or is it lndeed better for the mlnorlty and/or for falr representatlon to allocate seats by crlterla of geographlc conpactness (ln whlch case the mlnority rlll have no representatlve of lts own but perhaps partlal claim on the allegiance of three representatives)? Thls lssue ls dlrectly pendlng ln Seaman v. Upton, ln u.s. Distrlct court for the Eastern District of Texas, whlch deals wtrlch Texas congresslonal apportlorment. This and related lssues also arose directly ln Several cases that cane before federal courts ln the mld-7Os, with results that do not polnt c'learly ln a slngle dlrectlon.' The court's benl91 attltude toward blpartlsan grrynanderlng uas reasserted ln tihlte v. tleiser (412 u.S. 7S3 at 797-798 (1973)) ln whlch It held that drawlng dlstrtct boundarles'in such t way ts to mlnlnlze the nurnber Of contests between present lnCumbents does not ln and of Itself ertrbllsh lnvldlgsness.' lut ln Tavlor v. llcKclthen (t199 F. 2d .\ 893 (1971)) the Flfth Clrcult orployed the much weaker standards of a polltlcal access test to overturn a reapportlonment plan lmposed by the Unlted Strtes Dlstrict Court for the Eastern Dlstrlct of Loulslrna.5 Cttlng t{hitcomb for the proposltion that the Constltution' extendst!'f{Tlrotectlon of the Iaws to peop'le, not to lnterests, the Fifth Circult found no substantlal evldence that speclal black dlstrlcts were necessary to assure successful black partlclpatlon ln the polltlcal system (Do'l gor, 1977 z 466-477 l. tn the most important gemymandering case to date, United Jewish 0rganlzations of llllllancburg v. Carey 430 U.S. 144 (1976) orlglnally llted Jewlsh 0rganlzatlons of llllllamsburg v. !ilson, 510 F. 2d 5121, the Suprem Court ruled permlsslble a form of 'afflrmatlve actlon' gerrymanderlng. To correct alleged underrepresentatlon of black and Puerto Rlcan mlnorltles, certaln leglslatlve dlstrlct llnes ln New Yohk rere redrawn so as to create at least one state assembly dlstrlct ln Brooklyr rlth an overwhelmlng black and hlspanlc maJorlty. Previously blacks and hlspanics had been more or less evenly spread over the dlstrlcts ln qlestlon. In the process, a tlghtly knlt ultraorthodox counmlty of Hasldlc Jetrs, whlch had been contalned entlrely wlthln the boundarles of a slngle assembly dlstrlct wlth a 61.5 percent nonwhlte populatlon, was dlvlded lnto two dlstrlcts--one wlth an 88 percent nonrtrlte populatlon and the other rlth a 55 percent mlnorlty constltuency. The Court held that lt ras not lmpermlsslble for the state to drar llnes so as to correct lnvldlous dlscrlmlnatlon and that the plalntlffsr as *rlte votars, r€re not belng denled egal opportunlty for polltlcrl p.rtlclprtlon. l7 The Court's argument for lts declslon ln Unlted Jewish Organizatlons ls not, ln our view, a wel'l reasoned one. As Dolgow (1977:a78) notes, rBoth Unlted Jewlsh 0rganizatlons and Zinmer reflect a conceptlon of polltlcal particlpation that equates access t{lth 'wlnning' and 'rlnnlng' wlth electlng rmy own kind.,,, lle, on the other hand, share the vler of Trlbe (1978:658-659) that To speak of a group's electing 'lts' representative is,.after all, an oversiriplification. VarT6[s candidates appeal in va.ying degrees'to all population groups. 1!,: I minority mig"nt insuie some representation even in a district where it corlld not come close to electing a candidate who espoused its views without reservation; the minority could help elect the candidate whose views were least obnoxious to its members. 0f course, if there were clearly dichotomized minorities and majoritis5--and if voters never cast wayrvard ba'llots--the miiority might still be conpletely denied representation' 8ut these fictuil assumptions dify the facts of political life; there are many types of lnterests and many gradations,of , oplnion,with-theresultthataprocessofaccofilnodatlonrs oeneraliv undertaken ln which even small mlnorltles can iuccessfirllv vie for influence. llhlle the l,lil'll armburg case has been attacked as ref letting 'an underlylng assunptlon of the right to proportlonal representation' (Dolgow, 1977:4751, thls drastically overstates the nature of the Suprene cor:rt,s holdlng ln Il'l]lansh.,rg. Flrst, the Jurlsdlctlon was one coYered by the Federal votlng Rlghts Act, and this created a speclal presumptlon that .afflrmatlve actlon, might be called for. The Court',s seening support of afflrmative actlon gerrymanderlng ln Brooklyt should not be construed as necessarlly extendlng to Jgrlsdlctlons not covered by the Votlng Rlghts Act.6 Second, the nonwtrlte and hlspanlc popglatlon flgures ln the nerly created dlstrlcts glve the lnpresslon that these I l6 dlstrlcts ought lopsldedly to be under mlnorlty control. In fact, lf corrected for the proportlon of the populatlon whlch ls of votlng age (conslderably lower for hlspanlcs and blacks), thcn the dlstrlcts look cons I derably more competl tl ve ( Erlc Schnapper, personal conmunl catlon, June 13, 1980).' They 'look even more conpetltlve when we take lnto account loler mlnority turnout and the Ilkellhood that black voters and voters of Puerto Rlcan descent wlll not always vote as a bloc. Flnally, rhlle the Hasldlc Jerlsh Conmunlty hlthertofore had an Assembly dlstrlct to ltself, lts menbershlp had been dlvlded across other polltlcal boundarles (e.9,, U.S. Congresslonal dlstrlcts). 3. The Balloon Effect ,*r..orrnon, "ld vler that f6r slngle-member dlstrlcts ra chance pattern rlll, over the long haui, operate ln such a rray as to make the percentage of the populatlon and the percentage of representatlon more or less equal' (llelIs, 1979:529). However, for conplex statlstlcal reasons rhlch space llmltatlon prevents us frqn dlscusslng (see Tufte, 1973; llleml and Deegan, 1978; Grofman, 1982c forthcomlng), except under very speclal clrcumstances unllkely to be ever achleved ln practlce, random distrlctlng wlll not yleld proportlonallty between a group's vote percentage and the share of leglslatlrre seats lt wins. In partlcular, ln a tro-party ccmpetltlon lf partlsan.strength ls randomly dlstrlbuted rcross dlstrlcts (wlth a certaln speclfled varlance), then a random dranlng of dlstrlct llnes glves rlse to an expected S-shaped relrtlonshlp betreen prrty': aggregate vote share and lts share of leglslatlve seats. t. ',: t9 If ne let S be seat share and V vote share, thls seats-vote relrtlon- shlp ls rnll approximated by the functlon 1-S . l-v K . For K.3, u. SV have the so-called'cube law'of politics (Kendall and Stuart,1950). One lmpllcatlon of the "cube )ar' (or any K 01) ls wtrat Eackstrm, et al., (1978) have referred to as the'balloon effect,' ln whlch the leglslatlve power of maJorltles ls exaggerated and that of mlnorltles dg!g[399. (See Flgure l.) Flgure I about here The "balloo.n effectr wlll be less pronounced when minoritles are geographlcally concentrated. For a group with less than 50'percent votlng strength, to the extent that lts votlng strength ls geograhically concentrated lts seat share wlll, ln general, be more nearly proportlonal to lts vote share than would be predicted by the cube law. Ssne of its votes may be wasted by being concentrated ln lts om 'safe" districts, but thls waste ls overshadowed in lmportance by the posslbility of the mlnorlty concentratlng sufflclent of lts strengh to capture a number of distrlcts rather than wasting lts strength through dlspersion (Musgrove, 1977; l{lldgen and Engstrsn, 1980). Backstrcn, et al. (1978), Engstrm and lllldgen (1977) and tllldgen and Engstrcn (1980) have proposed to' .s measure falrness of apportlorment (1.e., proportlonallty between vote share and seat share) as re'latlrre to that rtrlch rould be statlstically exp€cted under a randqu drrwlng of cmprct and contlguons dlstrlct llnes' 18 20 given the actual geographlc pattern of mlnorlty and maJorlty populatlon dl spersion. lle anilclpate that wlth the lncreased sophlstlcatlon of polltlcal sclence models of seats-votes relatlonships (see esp. Tufte, 1973; Nleml and Deegan, 1978; Eackstrdfl, et al., 1978; Engstron and l{lldgen' 1977; ltlldgen and Engstrcm, l9S; Grofman, 1982c, forthcomlng), cmplex statlstlcal challenges to dlstrlctlng schemes based on thelr expected rrlal or partlsan lmpacts rtll be brought to the courts ln the 1980s. Such challenges rlll not rest on a demand for proportlonallty but rather on a demand for neutrallty and falrness. Even when crlterla such as equlpopulatlon, compactness' and contlngulty are all adhered to, contemporary technology stlll admltS a plethora of alternatlre dlstrlctlng schemes (see Backstrom et al., 1978). trloreover, re should emphaslze that contrary to popular bellef' one can't recognlze a polltlcal gerrymander by lts stppq. Cartography ls not what determines a gerrymander. One can have a gerrymander wlth dlstricts wtrlch appear on slght to be hlghly regular, and fair dlstrlctlng schemes which may appear to the eye to contaln grossly gerrymandered dlstrlcts. l{hat deflnes a gerrymander ls the fact that sone group or groups (e.9., a glven polltlcal party or a glven raclal/llngulstlc group) ls dlscrlmlnated against compared to one or mor€ other groups li that a greater number of votes ls needed for the former to achlevc t glwn proportlon of leglslatlve seats than ls true for the latter, and thls blas ls not on€ rhlch can be attrlbuted solely to the r,1 2l dlfferlng degree of geographic concentratlon among the groups (see especially Sickels, 1966; Musgove 1977)' Ingeneral'ltisourviewthatwhenthelmpactofadlstricting scheme (or electlon system) can be proJected (or Judged ln retrospect) wlth a very hlgh degree of certainty, schemes whlch can be shown to be grossly discrimlnatory ln thelr lmpact on the representation of cognlzable groups beyond what might reasonably be expected by chance should be struck down as unconstltutlonal. tte do not belleve that schemes whlch can't be dlrectly shown to have been l1!9g!!ong]]y gerrymandered ought therefore to have been made lnvlo'lable to constitutional chal1enge. At issr.e is (1) the theoretical problem of hot{ to measure extent of dlscrlmlnatlon and how to determine what constltutes @]-U slgrificant devlatlon and (2) how to reallstlcal'ly project 'hypothetlcal' electlon outcsnes. In thls context lt ls useful to conslder the Supreme Court's coment ln ttre 1973 case of Gaffrey v. Cunrnlngs (412 U.S. 735 at 752'753, enphasls added). It may be suggested that those who redistrict and reapportio-n shouli-work with census' not political, data and actrlbve population equalit.v without regard for. political. irnpuit. 'But this poiitica'ily mindless Spproach may produce' ;;ih;; i nten anceredwhether intendetf or-not' gros ffiint, it is most unlikely that the - -poiitiiit imiact of-such a plan wou'ld.remain, undiscovered by 22 rl. Cholce of Distrlctlng Hechanlsm lle share the preference of the late Robert Dlxon for a blpartlsan process of dlstrlctlng rather than for a process which has been (at least ostenslbly) polltlcally 'bllndfolded.' 0n thls topic, we can refer the author to Dlxon's own full masterful surmary 11979225-271' lle agree, too, wlth Dlxon that the agency responslble for dlstrlctlng ought not to be hanpered by rigld standards (e.g. maximizlng cmpactness) deslgned to ellmlnate all discretlon. Indeed, rlgld a prlorl 'technlcal' standards, whlch do not take lnto account the dlstribution of parHsanshlp and gnoup mernbdrshlp, nay be counterproductlve to the .Chlevement of 'falr and effectlve' representatlon. As Dlxon (1969:27) rlsely Puts lt: Loose guldes such as contlguity, observance of local pollttcal Oivisi6n llnes, and ccnpactness lnsofar as ccmpatibl.e wlth iiitr[ poputati6n equality are corrnonly mentioned and may be tuil'h-rxlf; h.8[f; .tr 8f, l[r 6f, ntn8'Ef Btlg[c. 3t'grriegy 15ements pol I tl ca'l rePresentatlon. In our vlew, the greatest rlsk ln a bipartlsan districtlng process ls that the dlstrlctlng that results wll'l be a 'blpartisan gerrymander,' 1.e., one xhlch seeks to preserve lncumbents of both parties and to drastlcally reduce the number of potentlally ccmpetltlve dlstrlcts. Such a gerrymander wou'ld vlOlate our bellef that 'seats ln a representatlve body sholld ching . . . atB vote totals change* (llleml and 0eegan' 1978:130{). Llkc llxon (1979:28-32) 11e applaud the emphrsls ln Gaffnev thrt dtttrlctlng ought to rYold nmuflcturlng a legt:lrtlve naJorlty gut 23 of a mlnority of the popular vote, but t€ are less sanguine than Diron that an unbiased but also largely uncompetitive set of dlstrlcts' such as that approved by the Court ln Gaffney, ls deslrable. Unfortunately' as noted prevlously, glven polltical and demographlc reallt{es ln the real rorld, no dlstrictlng syste,n can simultaneous'ly satlsfy all the criterla we mlght wish lt to (see Nleml and Deegan, 1978). liloreover, predlctlng the ten-year conseuences of a glven dlstrlctlng scheme'ls a vlrtual lmposslblllty. . In Connectlcut, the court-sanctloned oppose.d rbl-partlsan' gerrynander turned out to haw r dlstlnctly partlsar edge as the decade vore on. III. Electlon ilechanlsms other than Slngle-l{ember Dlstrlcts 0f the Justlflcatlons advanced for devlatlons fron the equal populatlon rule, the deslre to preserve local poltttcal boundarles ls the nost cormonly volced and the most frequently accepted. However, lf the deslre to preserve pollttcal boundaries ls made a maJor concern, then thls leads to conslderatlon of systems of representation other than slmple slngle-member dlstrictlng and ralses rea'l constitutlonal lssues as to what equal representatlon conslsts of. If polttlcal subunits aie of dlscrepant slzes, ln a slngle-member dlstrlctlng system sme smalI unlts wlll be denled thelr'own'representatlves, whlle sone larger unlts rlll bc dlvldrd up. Polltlcrl boundrrles crn b. ful'ly prescrved only by (f) ' allowlng for nultlple-member dlstrlcts (rfilch nqy use plurallty l'i 24 .at-large. votlng, or sme form of proportlonal representatlon), or (2) by uslng relghted votlng to cornpensate for populatlon dlfferences across polltlcal subunlts. t{hlIe stngle membershlp dlstrlctlng ls the most common form of representatlon ln the U.S., multlmember dlstrlctlng and mlxed slngle- and rnultlple-nrernber apportlorments are to be found ln varlous levels of goyerrment ln the U.S.; and ln one state (New York) weighted votlng ls the most cormon of the varlous systems ln use for county government. In the late 19[(},s and 70's such non-gnd systems have cone under lncreaSlng challenge as vlolatlng 14th Amendment 'egual protectlono standards. l. tlultlple-llember and At-Large Plurality-Based Electlons Apportlorment schemes at the state and local level often nrake use Of nultlmember dlstrlcts, the polar type of wttlch ls' of course! the at-1arge election. Such plans typlcally allocate the number of representatlws to a district ln direct proportlon to that distrlct's populaHon. In the aftermath of the supreme court's entrance into the 'polltlcal thlctet' of reapportlonment, the constltutlona'llty of nultlrnember dlstrlcts has recently been challenged on several grounds. Flrst, multlmember dlstr{cts are sald to submerge polltlcal law (or raclal/Ilngulstl c) ml norltl es. 7 Representatl ves frsn mul tlmember dlstrlcts are usually elected by tle same set of voters and often act as a bloc. Ghosen frsn the same constltuency' almost certalnly of the same party, the l&ntlty of lnterests among at-l57ge representstlves could be Gxp€ctcd to be geatcr thrn tho3c chosen fro dlstlnct dlstrlcts' and ?5 thus they probably wlll not ful'ly mlrror the vlers of all the cltlzens ln ' the constitrrncy (especlally those ln the overall voting mlnority). Second, ln multlmember dlstrlcts the tle between a representatlve and hls constituency ls weakened when a rroter does not have a slngle representat{ve to regard as trhi3 own.' (See Jeuett, 1982, forthcomlng.) A thlrd accusatlon agalnst multlmember dlstricts ls based on a mathematlcal argument, advanced by Banzhaf (1966; see Lucas 1974) rhlch clalms that resldents of smaller dlstricts are belng denied equal representatlon because resldents ln the larger dlstrlcts vho are electing representatlves proportlonal to thelr numbers have a more than proportlonate chance of affectlng electlon outcqnes. (Thls lssr.re and the mathematlcs underlying thls argument are dlscussed at length. ln Grofnan (1981(b)) and Grofman and Scarrow (1981(a).)8 In the first of the post-Baker cases challenglng multlmember dlstrlcts, Fortson v. 0orsey ((1965) 379 U.S. 433 ) the challenge ras related to the second argument we have noted above. The complalnt was that voters ln the Georgia legislature's slngle-member districts cbuld elect thelr own representatives; wtrlle voters ln the multimanber dlstrlcts (who elected representatlves at large but with the candidates requlred.to be resldents of a subdlstrlct, wlth each subdistrlct . allocated exactly one representatlre) were, lt was proposed, being denled thelr own representatlve, slnce voters frsn outslde the subdlstrlct ttelped to choose the subdistrlct's representatlve. 'The Court upheld Georgla's dlstrlctlng sJctcn, concludlng that voters ln multlmember . dlstrlcts dld lndeed elect thelr our rePresentttlv6-the representrtlY6 ir of the county, rather than of the suMlstrlct ln whlch they happened to reslde' (Trlbe, 19782752, emphasls ours). In Fortson (379 U.S. 433) the Supreme Court h6ld (as lt niA tn Reynolds at 577.) that 'equal protectlon does not necessar{ly requlre formatlon of all slngle-member dlstrlcts ln a state's leglslatlve apportlorment scheme.' The Corrt asserted ln Fortson (379 U.S. at 439 that 'the leglslatlve cholce of multimember districts ls subJect to constltutlonal cha'llenge only upon a showlng that the plan was deslgned to or vould operate to mlnlmlze or cancel out the votlng strength of raclal or pol{tlcal groups,'a vlen lt reafflrmed ln the next case to coile up on thls lssue (Burns v. Rlchardson (1965) 384 U.S. 74). The challenge to the multimember apportlorment scheme ln the next naJor case ln thls area, l{hltcqnb v. Chavis, 403 U.S. 124 (1971), rested on wtrat we have ldentlfled above as arguments one and three. Flrst, lt ras alleged that l,tarlon the county multimember distrlct 'lllegally mlnlmlzes anM cancels out the votlng power of a cognlzable raclal mlnorlty ln Harlon Countf (403 U.S. at 144). Thls clalm ras reJected by the Cqrt on the grounds of an lnadequate showlng as to the facts. Second, lt ras clalmed (based on the argument ln 8anzhaf,1965) that 'rotlng power does not vary lnversely wlth the slze of the distrlct and that to lncrease leglslatlve seats ln proportlon to lncreased populatlon gl*s undue votlng power to the votlr ln the multimember dlstsrlct slnce he has more chances to detennlne electlon outcmes than does the voter ln the slngle-nrember dlstrlct' (403 U.5. at 144-145). Thls second argument rac rlso reJected by the Suprene Court, ln frct, qulte declslvely and 27 lndeedderlslvely.However,lnt,lhltccmbthecourtcontlnuedtoassert tht the constitutlonality of multimember dlstrlctlng could be challengd on a case-bY-case basis. In llhite v. Regester 412 U.S. 766 (1973), the u.s. suprerne court foundthatmultimemberdlstrlcts,asdeslgnedandoperatedlnEexar county, lnvldious'ly excluded b'lacks and Hexlcan-Amerlcans frcm polltlcal participatlonrandthatslngle-memberdlstrlctswererequiredtoremedy theeffectsofpastandpresentdlscrimlnatlonagalnstblacksand l,lexlcan.Americans.Inl,rlhitetheCourt.llveduptoltspromiselnFortson and Lltrltcom! that a properly mounted challenge to multlmember dlstrictlng, when sustained by a historlca.| record of discrlmlnatlon' could, ln fact, succeed. In subsequent cases, scme apportionments whlch make use of multlmember distrlcts have been struck down as unconstltutiona'l by the federal courts, usually ln sltuations wtrere there was a we'll docunented record of prevlous. discrimlnation, and a record of raclally or lingulstlcal]ypolarizedvoting;butthecourtshavereiteratedthat multimember dlstrlcts are not per se unconstitutional. However. the Supreme court (ln connors v. Johnson 402 U.S. 690 (1971) and chaPotan v. ileler 420 U.S. 1 (1SZS) nas lndlcated a presumptlon against ,court-ordered mu]tlmernber distrlct plans ln the absence of exignt clrcumstances? (Trlbe 1978:755, emphasis ours); wtrile the votinq Rights Acthas,s'lncetheearlylgT0s,beensoconstruedbytheJustlce DepartmentastovlrtuallybanaJurlsdlctloncoveredbytheActfr@ renlaclnq slngle-member. dlstrlcts wlth nultlnenber ones (see Engstro' 26 28 igZg), although sme shlfts frm an at-large electlons to mlxed slngle member dlstrlcts and at-large electlons have been allowed. In the most lmportanat case on multimember dlstrlctlng declded to date,g the Supreme Canrt ln Clty of t'lob'lle A'labama v. Bolden (48 L.t{. 4435, 1980) ruled (ln a 6-3 vote wlth Justlces Brennan, llhlte, and llarshall dlssentlng) that an at-large e'lection system ln Moblle did not unfairly dllute black votlng strength--overturnlng a lower court ru]lng whlch reqglred l,loblle to ellmlnate lts present form of (commlsslon-based) goverrment and swltch to slngle-member dlstrlcting. The facts ln the I'loblie case are not really ln dlspute. Under the ar-large system for clty councll electlons, because of a pattern of racllally po]arlzed bloc votlng, black electoral success was nll' desplte b'lack's constltutlng a masslve populatlon mlnority ln the clty. There exlsted a clear hlstory of raclal dlscrlmination ln the city as wel1. The key questlon at lssue ln Hobile was whether there had to be proof of dlscrlmlnatory lntent. Justlce Stewart. (Joined by Justlces Burger' Powell and Rehnquist), followlng a llne of reasonlng lald down ln Vlllage u.s. 252, sald that there had to be prnposeful discriminatlon. Howeven' there rere flve addltlonal separate opinlons ln Mobl'le ln addltlon to the four member plurallty oplnlon; and lt ls dtfficult to be sure what, lf any, clear guldellnes have been laid down ln thls case. It does appear' however, that before repudlatlng a multlmember systen, r mdorlty of the present court wlll elther requlre very hlgh standards of proof of dlscrlnlnatory lg!g! (the four Justlces ln the 29 plurallty) or allow to pass constitutlonal muster any scheme xhich is supported by any neutral Justsificatlon, 1.e., any votlng scheme rhlch ls not entirely motlvated by a deslre to curtall the polltical strength of the mlnorlty (Justlce Stevens). Giren such strlngent criterla, far lf any, multlmober districting schemes would be declared unlawful. tloreover, the one holdlng on whlch there was a clear mqfority ln Moblle was that the impact standards enunciated by the Fifth Clrcuit Court of Appeals ln Zirmer v.!q[qi!!g! 467 F. 2d 1381 were lnsufflclent by themselves to establlsh a prima facle case for lntentlonal dlscrlmlnation. It was under these standards that many of the mu'ltlnembr dlstrlctlng s.chemes prevlously repudl ated as unconstitutlonally dlscriminatory had been Judged (see Grofman, 1982, forthcoming). The I'lobi'le case ls a very troubllng one ln a number of ways. Flrst, we prefer the repudiated standaards of Zinmer to those enunciated ln any of the concurring oplnlons ln Mobi'le. The prevaillng standards ln l{oblle wlll perpetuate election systems whlch severely handicap black and hlspanlc electoral success, 6peclally at the munlcipal lerel.l0 Second, we flnd the plurality oplnlon remarkably sophlstic ln lts claim that lts vlews ln the Mobile declsion are fully consistent rlth earller declslons iuch as Fortson v. Dorsey and Whlte v. Regester. In particular, the Ianguage of Fortson (379 U.S. at 439, enphasls added) ls c'tear that the 'cholce of multlmember dlstrlcts ls subJect to challenge oniy rpon a show'lng that the plan was deslgned to or would operate to mlnlnlze or cancel out the votlng strength of raclal or polltlcal groups.' Slnllarly, as Justlce llhlte scathlngly polnts out ln hls \ of Arlinoton tleiqhts v. Iitan Houslnq Devel ration, 429 30 Otssent ln lloblle, the standards .nr*rated by the Flfth Clrcult Court of Appeals ln Zirmer rere derlved directly frqn the Supreme Court's own language ln llhlte v. Regester and }lhltccnb v. Chavis Thlrd, the absence ln Moblle of any constltutlonal prlnclples on rhlch a maJorlty could clearly agree mean that we can expect confllctlng declslons frcm the lower courts on the constltutlonallty of partlcular electlons systems rhlch make use of multlmember dlstrlcts or at-large el ectl ons . l1 '/ 2. l,leighted Voting, Approval Votlng, the Alternatlrre Vote, and Proporti onal Representat I on Slngle-nanrber dlstrlcts may be used ln conJunctlon with welghted votlng, or vlth approval votlng or the alternatlre rot.l2 replaclng a. simple pltnallty rule. Each of those modiflcatlons to the usual electlon procedures has varlous advantages and various dlsadvantages. Space llmltatlons, however, prevent us dlscusslng these alternatlve electlon mechanlsms ln any detall. (See Rae, 1971; Grofman, 1975, 1981(a), 1981(b) and varlous essqys ln Grofman et al. 1982 forthcomlng.) In welghted votlng, rather than there belng, say, a representatlve for every ten thousand voters, representatlves receive votes ln the leglslature whlch are a functlon of the populatlon they represent' e.g.' one weighted vote for each ten thousand voters ln thelr constltuency.' Thls devlce ras adopted ln tln 196G by a nunber of llew York countles rtrlch had prevlously elected r county board of supervlsors comlttlng of ona raprGantrtlya frcn each tornrhlp regrrdl.st of tornshlp 3l populatlon--a form of unit votlng system struck dom by the New York courts ln 1965. t{elghted votes ln all the Netl York counties to adopt welghted votlng'ln the 60s were allocated dlrectly Proportlonal to the populatlon belng represented. In an important case ln the late 60's' Iannucci v. Board of Supervlsors of the County of Uashington (282 ll.Y. 2d. 5021, the llew York court of Appeals held that weighted votlng ras permlsslble only if the welght asslgments were such as to girre rise to Banzhaf power values for each leglslator exactly proportlonal to the population he/she represents. Such Banzhaf power scores are based on a game-theoretic notlon of 'declsiven votes--votes which could change the outcome (see Banzhaf, 1965, 1966; Brans, 1975; Lucas, 1974; Grofman and Scarrm, 1980, 1981(a,b)). In general, the welghts which optimize the flt between a leglstor,s Banzhaf power score and the slze of the constltuency he represents wil'l be very close to welghts assigned on the basls of a slmple llnear proportionallty between a leglslator reighted vote and the population he represents. uhile weighted voting as used in Ner York counties permlts huge dlscrepancles (as much as 100 to 1) between the weights of the legislator frm the Iargest and the smal'lest units belng represented, lt does have the strlklng advantage of also permittlng polltlcal subunlts (townshlps ln the case of Nen York county gverrunent) to stay lntact and to each have a representatlve of lts om. tlelthted votlng has not, to our knowledg, been used ln local goverrments outslde of the state of tler York, but lt ls avallable as a devlce yhlch could be consldered ln post' 1980ir r.gapportlomcntl--llthough tts conrtltutlonallty hrs never been 32 subJect to test ln federal courts. Its best potentlal use, ln our vlfl, rould be where subunlts were not wldely discrepant ln sl:e (e.9., populafion ratlos of less than 2 to 1). Its use ln such cases has been strongly advocated by Professor Lee Papayanopoulos (persona'l comnunlcatlon, June 15, 1980), who has served as a consultant to most of the Nen York countles wtrlch have adopted weighted voting' Approvalvotlng(BramsandFlshburn,lgTS)permltseachvotertocast as many ballots as there are candidates, less one' 8y votlng for a candldate,avoterlsexpres.slngwllllngnesstoseethatcandidate elected. The candidate l|lth the geatest number of 'approval' votes ls decl ared el ected. Erans and Flshburn (1978) shcw that approval votlng has a nunber of nlce propertles. One of the deslrable characteristics of approva'l votlng lsthatltrendersmorellkelytheselectionofanmajorlt/.winner.A rmaJorltf rlnner ls simply that candidate, if any' rrho could recelve a maJorlty ln a head-on-head contest agalnst each of the other candidates' CIearly, a maJorlty wlnner (lf one exlsts) satisfies our lntultlve not,lons of wtrat ls meant by a 'maJorltf cholce (Black, 1958; Grofman' lggl(d) forthccrnlng). conslder the Goodell vs. Buckley vs. otlnger New York senatorlal vote. Buckley won wlth only about 40 percent of the vote. If 0Hnger werenrt ln the race, Goodell would have beaten Buckley' since llberal Democrats would have.voted for Goodell ln preference to.the conservatlre Buckley. 0n the other hand, lf Buckley had not been ln the raccr lt lr vary llkcly thrt Goodell hluld havc berten 0tlnger"stnce 1016 con3cryttlyt Yote6 rould htvc problbly Yoted for thc Republlcrn 33 candldate, Goodell, rather than the Democrat, 0tlnger, even thougir both candldates were popularly ldentified as strong llberals. Eecause Goodell could have beaten either of hls opponents ln a head-on-head contest, he ls what we have been referrlng to as a Condorcet wlnner. 0f course, ln the actual race, he'lost. Had voters cast approval votes, lt ls llkely that many llberals rnuld have voted for both Goodell and 0tinger, that strong conservatives wou'ld have voted for Euckley only, and that sqne Republlcan conservatlves would have voted for Goodell as well. Since llberal voters in thls race outnumbered conservatlve ones and Republlcan voters outnumbered Democratlc ones, lt ls llkely that Goode'll uould have been elected had approval voting been used for thls race. The alternatirre vote ls another mechanism which has been proposed to cope wlth multicandldate races in which the plurallty choice may be other than the Condorcet w'lnner. Under the alternatlve vote, voters are asked to rank order all candidates. AII flrst-place votes are counted. If no candidate receives a maJority of flrst-place votes, the Imest candldate ls dropped and hls/her votes real'located to the second cholce candldates on those ballots whlch had deslgated him a first choice. The process of dropplng the lowest.candldate frcm the race and reallocating votes contlnues, until one candidate has recelved a maJority. It can be shom (Grofman, 1975) that under reasonable assumptlons the alternatlve vote makes lt more llkely that r'maJorltya dnner wlll be chosen. In the Goodell-Buckley-0tlnger senatorlal contest, the alternatlve vote uould llkely have led to the cholce of Otlnger. No candldatc rec€lwd r mrJorlty.,of flrrt-plrce cholcosr Goodell rocelved the feuest flrst cholce 34 votes, and most Goodell voters would have had 0Hnger as thelr second cholce. Thus, ln thls case, the maJority winner would not have been chosen; however, the perverse result of a candldate (Buckley) belng chosen *ro was not preferred to elther of hls opponents whould have been avoi ded. The a'lternatlrn vote has been used ln a fen ciiles (mosily *college towns') but has never caught on as a voilng reform--posslbly because the rank-ordered ballot compllcates voter cholce and the transfer procedures conslderably ccnpllcate the vote tallylng process. Proportlonal representation, although the most common elecfion mechanism ln dernocratlc soclefies, ls largely foreign to the U.S. electora'l erperlence. Llke most Engllsh speaklng nations, vlrtually all electlons ln the u.S. make use of slmple plurallty declslon-maklng..Only s]lghtly over two dozen u.S.'cltles have ever made use of pR (ln the forn of the Hare slngle transferable vote)--most durlng the perlod 19ls-1945. crrently only canbridge (for both munlclpal and school board electlons) and llew York (for school board elecHcns only) make use of the Hare system. However, frsn 1870-1980 the lower house of the Illinols teglslature was electei frcrn 3-member dlstrlcts uslng cunulailve voilng, a form of proportlonal representatlon. 13, 14 tlhlle pR has been voclferously attacked as leadlng lnevitably to factionallsm and a breakdown of stable maJorlty gove.rrment, the u.S. experlence wlth the Hare spten and wlth cumulatlrre votlng has been largly poslilve. pR.s fallure to catch on {n the u.s., and lts repudlailon ln vlrtually rll the Jurlsdlctlon: drlch used lt, can be attrlbuted to a varlety of 35 factors--few lf any of which have anythlng to do with its actual merits' (See Grofman, 1982(a) forthcoming.) tlhile early in this century the slngle transferable vote xas struck down by the courts ln scrne Jurlsdlctions on the grounds that lt vlolated constltutlonal or charter provlslons wtrich gave cltizens the right t0 vote for the candidates of their choice, there are no recent cases challenging lts 'legitimacy. Ilhi'le federal courts have repudiated the doctrlne that groups have an a prlorl rlght to proportlonal representation, ln our vlew lt ls unljkely that statury adoption of PR would be blocked on "one man' one vote" grounds. He believe that the present-day concern for effective mlnorlty representation ought to 'lead to renewed lnterest in proportional representatlon. There are, however, aS yet no signs of such a PR revlval at the local or state Ievel and, lndeed, cumulative voting has Just been ended ln Il'llnols.15 In the Democratlc party, however, winner-take-all prlmarles have been replaced by a form of proportlonal representatlon ln the presldentlal nqnlnatlng process, and mlnorlty guotas (or goals) for &legate selectlon have been adopted. V. CONCLUSIONS cases lnvolvlng reapportlonment deal wlth one of the fundamental problems of democratic theory--the nature of 'falr and effectlve' representatlon. Reapportlorunent lltlgatlon ls an area uhich ccmblnes legal scholarshlp on the expllcatlon of constltutlonal prlnclp'les rtth' 35 the use of statlstlcal technlques to analyze case-speclflc data. Soclal sclence research on the lmpllcatlons of alternailve dlstrlcHng p'l ans/electoral systerm, whether ln the context of the speclfic f actua'l clrcumstances of a partlcular case or ln terms of abstract models of trade-off relatlonshlps anong confllctlng dlstrlcilng crlterla, can plqy an lmportant ro1e ln aldlng Judges to resolve the consiltutional and erplrlcal questlons that wlll be at lssue in the reapporHorynent lltlgatlon of the 1980s. In the 1980s the equal populailon standard wlll be taken for granted. The key quesilons whlch the courts wlll confront rl't'l be much subtler, €.9., (t) How do we measure polltlcal gerrymanderlng and establlsh standards as to when gerrymanderlng has exceeded constltutlonally permlsslble limlts? (2) llow do we detemlne xhen nonslngle-merber dlstrlct electlon mechanlsms have unconstltutlonally'submerged' or ncllutedu the vofing strength of raclal or other mlnorltles? (3) How do we reconclle confllcfing consiltuilonal or statutory dlstrlctlng criteri a? l{e believe that soclal sclence research can be useful to the courts ln clarifylng the value cholces that must be made ln provldlng standards of statlstlcal measurement for concepts (such as gerrymanderlng), whlch are at present qulte fuzzl'ly deflned at best. llhlle the existence of clear and wldely acceptable statlsfical measures of gerryrnandering and/or vote dllutlon rould certalnly have b'een no panacea for the dlfflcult declslons confronted by the court ln cases llke clty of l.toblle v. Bolden (1980) or gaffney v. Cunmlngs (1973), and rlhllc such mc{ures of effect (or expected effeet) do not dlrectly address the lssue of lntent to '37 discrlminate, ntrich has been emphasized on recent cases such as Hobile; nonetheless, it seems clear to us that, as y1e move into the 1980's, U.S. courts would be helped (especially ln cases lnvolving alleged racial or partisan gerrymandering) by the development of statistica'l technlques to csnpare expected outccmes of partlcular dlstrlctlng/e'lectoral scheroes 11lih the outcomes that mlght be expected glven rneutral' slngle-mea$er d I strl ctl ng . Footnotes Scholars ln other Engllsh-speaking democracies shake thelr heads ln dlsbe'llef that U.S. courts should have been so aIl-consumed with questlons of mathematlcal precislon ln populatlon equality. Canadlans have long recognized that a leglslative dlstrlct located ln a dense unban area ls easler to represent ln the Canadian House of Cornons than ls a dlstrlct in the Pralrie provinces whose dimensions are measured ln thousands of square mlIes. Hence Canadlans don't worry that one dlstrict may be 25 percent smaller ln populatlon than another. Brltishers have acknowledged that t.lelshmen and Scotsmen are outnumbered by Englishmen by a margin of 9 to 1, and they have conc'luded that the House of Conmons ls a better. representatlve body lf thosi cultural mlnoritles are allowed to elect representatives ln greater number than a strict populatlon formula would a'llow. In other yrords, Canadians and Britons have attorpted to csne to grlps rtth the conplex and admlttedly dlfficult questlon of'representatlon rather than to be consurned by the quest for mathematlcal equal ity. tle mlght further extend the argument lf we assume that both dlstrlcts are equally conpetltlve but that the lncumbent leglslator ln one dlstrlct, thanks to hls sen{orlty, heads a powerful cofinittee, whlle the other ls only a freshmen leglslator. An exrnplc of such leglslatlon li H. R. 11516 (96th Congresr, lst Scsrlo, ,lrnuuy a5, 1979), drlrrn up ulth Comnon Clute supportr 39 whlch requlres (a) that single-member dlstrlcts satlsfying equal populatlon guldellnes (permlttlng only a 2 percent dlscrepancy frm strl ct equallty), (b) that the boundarles of each distrlct shall {consistent with the equal populatlon requlrement) colnclde rith the boundarles of local subdivisions, (c) ttrat each dlstrlct shall be ccmposed of contlguors territorles, (d) that districts shall be conpact ln form, (e) ttrat the boundarles of districts may not be drawn for the purpose of favoring any polltlcal party or any speciflc incumbent or any other lndivldual, and (f) that the boundarles of a dlstrlct may not be drarm for the purpose of dlluting the votlng strenth of any language minorlty group or of any raclal minorlty group. (See Conmon Cause, 1977; Adams, 1977.1 4. Recall that single-member dlstrlctlng wlll not ln general achieve aggregate proportionality between a party or group's vote share and Its share of leglslative seats. 5. The factors relied upon by the court to reach this conclusion lncluded "the shrinklng rrhlte populatlon, the lncreaslng black populatlon, and the accelerating black reigstratlon" ln 0rleans Parlsh. Since thb three districts with rtrite mqiorlties would still have substantlal nonwhite cormunltles, blacks would be assured 'a volce ln the politlcal processes" (![ at 9OZ). Emphasis was also placed upon the fact that r black senator had been elected ln one of the dlsputed dlstrlcts, although black reglstratlon ln that dlstrlct x$ under flfty percent, 8y cmgarlsm, the dlstrlct court'r plan I 38 1. 2. 3. 6. 40 vlrtually assured whlte control ln tro dlstrlcts for the foreseeable future. So great was the whlte maJorlty ln these leglslatlve seats that the 'ytlte senators frcrn these dlstrlcts could lgnore wlth lmpunlty the speclal needs of blacks ln those distrlcts" (Id at 902)' 0f course, lf you don't like the t{illiarmburg rullng thls may be scant consolatlon. The Votlng Rights Act now covers 25 states ln whole or ln part. (See ttollock, 1980, for detalls.) It explres ln 1982, and the flght over lts renewal ls expected to be lntense (Joaqutn Avlla, Mexlcan-Amerlcan Legal Defense and Educatlonal Fund' personal cormunlcatlon, llovember 1980). CIearly, the nature of polltlcal and demographlc realltles wlll determlne the extent to which slngle-member or multimember dlstrlctlng wlll help or hlnder particu'lar politlcal, raclal, or rellglous mlnorltles. If a mlnorlty ls reasonab'ly large and geographically concentrated, it may expect to get lts "ovin" representatlve(s) ln a sinqle-member distrlct but might be swamped by other groups lf forced to conpete for representatlon ln a very large mu'ltimember.dlstrlct. 0n the other hand, if a mlnorlty ls not geographically concentrated and lf lt has some political 'clout,' lt may be far mre effectlve ln a larger mu'ltlmember unlt where lt may be granted sme representatlon, perhaps even representatlon proportlonal to lts numbers,. than engaged ln ftghtlng and loslng a ncnber of struggles for control of slngle-member dlstrlcts. (Cf. dlscusslon ln Carpenettl, 1972.) thnetheless, the avallable cnplrlcrl evldence ls wlte strong that, at least for munlclprl 41 electlons, mlnority representatlon ls considerably more proportlonal ln ward-based cities than in cltles with at-large elections. Particularly strlking is the evidence based on before-and-after cunparisons of cities wtrlch shlfted frcrn at-large to district-based electlons. (See Grofman, 1981a forthcomlng, and references thereln.) Itultlmernber dlstricts have, however, not been without their defenders. Around the turn of the century replacing district systems wlth at-large elections was the goal of munlcipal refomers anxlous to break the power of "wardo politicians. A number of scholars, such as Bryce (1889:463-64; cited in Klain' 1955:1118)' deplored the spread of single-member districts' holding them responslble for the decline ln quallty of state 'legisl.atures. Thc area of cholce being smaller, 'lnferlor men are chosen.' For a more detalled discussion of the lssues ln the slngle-member versus multimember controversy, see Grofman (I981 forthcoming and appendlx thereto, available upon request frqn the author ). l,lobiIe lnvol,red a cormisslon form of government wtrlch mingles leglslative and administratlve functlon, and lt has been suggested that "as a direct precedent for multimember state legislatlve dlstricts, the Mobile case may nell be lrrelevant' (Burks, Epsteln, and Allto, 1980:29). Nonetheless, as these authors 90 on to say' the Constltutlonal prlnclples on whlch t'lobile was decided are 'those that wlll contlnue to govern leglslatlve and congresslonal '.L, redlstrlctlng ctses to come.r Ie should also note that there are ''' .\ 8. 7. 9. tt342 ' lEDorttnt dlfferences b.ty€an casas tltc lgllE, brought aa 12. Th€ alternitlve vot€ ls tha slngla tr.nsfa.abh rotr r.ttrlcted to. aoni tsitonat ch.Ilenlei, and claaa trought und€r tha votlng Rtghtt slngle-nent€r d'lstrlct' lct, for *rt.h dtffefent *rndn.ds nry apply (tea crofflan, tr8l., 13' lie ui' the terin proportlonll repr$ent'tlon to r.fcr to th' lor fuller dtacu33ion) rtrElple th.t the dlstrtbuiton of lagtrlatura ie.tr should lo. Th. coo. tuHonrltty of r|lll m. ber el€cHon3 tr of p.rHculrr , corEsrond rlth the dlstrlbutlon of th! poDular vota for lcqlalatlv! . Goncara at the locrl lcva! of goverrnent slnce norc thu 60 p€rcent cindldates' ot u.s. cltl€s and abo{t one thlrd of t 's. coontle! use rn rt-lrrla 14'' ln llllnols lsseflbly taccsr voter3 llerc glvln 3 voter rhlch th€y r'y ryit€Ir tnd a rlgniflcant pr€p...tlon of tha reIlalnlng cltles r dlvlded equilly 'mong 3 crndl'te! (on€ vote G!ch)' dlvld! 'qu'Ilv countlci ui. r lr of slngl. .nd [ulthrErber dlatrlct! (&v€ll, ' rmng 2 ctndld'tes (on' 'nd i hrlf votes etch)' ot glven 'xclusfvlly l9r1i x.. .fi/s, l97g). to ono c.ndld.te (rho rec.'lver rll 3 votes). ctirulrtlv. votlng r.t lr. rhcra are . ru b€r ot consfltufional subfl.fi.s rn th€ lrobfle caia o used ln th€ prln'ry rtclt for Ailenbly .€'tt' $rch our drlc1rlsrdr omrts .nfiEryr ..g., tho draHnc on b.t*.n l5' A 'efetinfur to rcduce the 'lre o' th' lo*r houre' rfilch 'l5o caiaa undcr tha Fourteenth &Endrent .nd c.ses under thc Ftft..nth 'lltrln't'd curul'tlti rotlngr crrfl'd ln xovsrb'r 1980' lfiendient (aec Bu'ls, Epsteln, rnd Atlto, l9O:$-33). Th! l,lobile cale llselt has be€n remanded to a lomr court for furthar rrgu@nt as to lpproprlrte reredy ind a n€r, lmportrnt casc ylll ba bafore tha U.S, Suprglle Corrt ln l9@, Rog€rs v. Lodqe (formerly Lodge v. Burton, Fifth Circuit, Slip t{o. 78-3241) whlch offers the doctrlne that a substantlal and apparent dlscriminatory effect whlch has exlsted over a long perlod of time and has not been redressed, shou'ld be treated as prlma facle evldence of lntent to dlscrlminate. If tils doctrlne ls accepted, mlnorltles say be able to 6cOG frsr the Jaws of iloblle. 4514 References Adarns, Bruce 'A l,lodel State Reapportlotent Process: The Contlnulng Quest for rFalr and Effectlve Representatlon.'' Harvard Journal on Legislatlon' Vol. 14, No. 4 (June 1977), pp. 825-904. Auerbach, Carl A. 'The Reapportionment Cases: One Person, One Vote - One Vote' One Value.' In Phllip Kurland (Ed.), Supreme Court Revlew. Chlcago: Unlrrerslty of Chlcago Press, 1964, pp. 1-87. Sackstron, Charles, Leonard Roblns, and Scott Eller 'lssues ln Gerrymanderlng: An Exploratory l,leasure of Partlsan Gerrymanderlng Applled to illnnesota.r lt'llnnesota Law Revlew Vol. 52 (1978), pp. 1121-59 Banzhaf, John F. III 'tleighted Voting Doesn't lJork: A ilathenatlcal Analysls.' Rutgers Lar Levlevr, Vol 19 (1965)' pp. 317-343. Banzhaf, Johd F. III 'l.lu ltl -Member El ectoral 0ne-Vote' Prl ncl pl e?r Blcker, Itilllam E. 'The Effects of Halapportlonment ln the States--A Histrlal.' In Nelson Polsby (Ed.)' Reapportionment ln the 1970s- Berkeley: University of Callfornla Press, 1971, pp. 151-201. Black, Duncan The Theory of Cormlttees and Electl.ons. New York: Cambrldge University Press, 1958. Blalr, G. S. Cumulative Voting: An Effectlve Electoral Devlce ln Illinols Po'litics. Champalgn, Illlnols: Unlverslty of Illlnols Press, 1950. Blalr, G. S. 'Cumu'latlve Votlng: An Effectlve Electoral Devlce for Fair and llinority hepresentation.' In Lee Papayanopoulos (Ed.).' Democratle Representation and Apportionment. Ner York: Nu York Academy of Sciences, 1973, pp. n-26, Brady, David and Richard Murray 'Reformers and Skeptics. Testlng for the Effects of Apportlonment Patterns on Pollcy 0utputs.r In l,l. Holden, R. ilathew' and D. Dresange (Eds.), lJhat Goverrunent Does, Beverly Hll'ls: Sage Publlcations' 1975. 8rarm, Steven J. Gane Theory and Polillcs. llew York: Free Press, 1975. Bram, Steven J. The Presldentlal Electlon Game. tlfl Haven' Conn.: Yale Unlrerclty Press,1978. Dlstrlcts--Do They Vlolate the rOne- l'lan' Yale Law Journal, Vol. 75 (1966), pp. Analysls of the Electoral 13 (1968), pp. 314-332. 1309-1338. Eanzhaf, John F. III '0ne llan, 3,312 Votes: A l,lathematlcal College.' Vlllanova Lar Revlew, Vol. 1745 8iams, Steven J. 'Approval Votlng.' In B. Grofman, A. LlJphart, R. McKly' and H. Scarrow (Eds.), Representatlon and Redlstricllng Issues., Lexlngton 8ooks, 1982 forthcomlng. 8rams, Steven J. and Peter C. Flshburn. 'Approval Votlng.' lmerican Polltlcal Sc'lence Revlew' Vol. 72' No. 3, (Sept. 1978), PP. 831-847. Bryce, James B. The Anerlcan Csnnonnealth, Vol. I. New York: l'lacmillan, 1889. 8rks, Phtllp E., Davld A. Epsteln' and Sanuel A. Allto. 'Federal Case Larr: State Leglslatlve and Congresslonal Dlstrictlng.' In A. llo'tlock (Ed.), Reapportlonnent: Law and Technology. Denver: l{atlonal Conference of State Leglslatures' 199), pp.5-52. Carpenettl, l{alter L. 'Leglslatlve Apportionment: l.lultlmenber Dlstrlcts and Falr Representatlon.' Unlversity of Pennsylvanla Law Revlew' Vol. 120 ll972l, pp'. 665-700 Casper, Gerhard 'Apportloment and the Rlght to Vote: Standards of Judlclal Scrutlny.r Supreme Court Revia (1973)' pp. l-33. Ccmon Cause Reapportlonment: A Better llay. A Cqnmon Cause Proposal. tlashlngton, 0.C.: Coamon Cause. t{ovenber 1977. Dlxon, Robert G., Jr. Democratic Representation and Reapportlonment ln Lan and Polltlcs. New York: 0xford Universlty Press, 1958. Dlxon, Robert G., Jr. "The Warren Court Crusade for the Holy Grall of '0ne Han-0ne Vote." Supreme Court Revlew (1969), 9p. 219-270. Dlxon, Robert G., Jr. 'The Court, The People, and 'One Man,One Vote.'' In llelson l{. Polsby (Ed.), Reapportionment ln the 1970's. Eerkeley: Unlverslty of Callfornla Press, 1971, pp. 7-45. Olxon, Robert G. Jr. nReapportionment and Equallty of Polltlcal 0pportmlty.' : Unpublishbd manuscript, 0ctober 19, 1979. Olxon, Robert G., Jr. 'Falr Crlterla and Procedures for Establlshlng Leglslatlve Dlstrlcts." In B. Grofman, A. LlJphart, R. McKay, and H. Scarror (Eds.). Eepresentation and Redistricting Issues. Lexington Books' . 1982 forthcoming. Reprlnted fron Pollcy Studles Journal, speclal I ssue , l.larch 1981 . Dlxon, Robert G., Jr. 'Crlterla for D.istrictlng.' In 8. Grofman, A. LlJphart, R. HcKly' and h. Scarrow (Eds.). . Lexlngton, 1982 forthcomlng. It9 48 Dodd, Lawrence Coalltlons ln Parllanrentary Government. Prlnceton, ll.J.: Prlnceton Unlverslty Press, 1976. Dolgor, Samuel R. . 'Polltlcal Representatlon: The Search for Judlclal Standards.' Brooklyn Lar Revlew, Vol. 43 (1977), pp. 431-487. Engstrm, Rlchard L. 'The Supreme Court and Equl-Populous Gerrymandering: A Remalnlng 0bstacle ln the Quest for Falr and Effectlve Representatlon.r Arlzona State Law Journal, Vol. 1976, No. 2 (1977),9p.277-319. Engstran, Rlchard L. 'Racla'l Vote Dllutlon: Supreme Court ln Interpretatlons of Sectlon 5 of the Voting Rlghts Act.' Southern Unlverslty Law Revlew, Vol. 4, l{o. 2 (Sprlng 1978), pp. 139-163. Engstron, Rlchard L. and John K. llildgen 'Prtnlng Thorns frqn the Thlcket: An Emplrlcal Test of the Exlstence of Raclal Gerrymandering.' Legislatlve Studles Quarterly, Vol. 2, ilo. 4 (November 1977), pp. 465-479 Erlckson, Robert 'The Partlsan Impact of Reapportlonment.' l,lldwest Journal of Politlcal Sclence, Vol. 57 (1971), pp. 57-71. Grofman, Bernard 'A Revla of l.lacro-Electlon Systems.' In Rudolph lllldenrnann (Ed.)' Gennan PolItlcal Yearbook (SozlalrlssenschaftlIches Jahrbuch fur Polltlk), Vol. 4. llunlch Gernany: Verlrg, 1975, pi. 303-352. Grofman, Bernard 1'Alternatlvei to Stnste-Member Plurality Districts: Legal and Emplrlcal Issues.' Policy Studles Journal. Special lssue on ,,ieapportionment Pollcy,' April 198f(a). Reprinted ln 8. Grofoan' A. LiJphart, R. McKay and H. Scarror (Eds.)' Representation and Redlstricting Issues. Lexing'.on: 1982, forthcming. Grofman, Bernard "Falr and Effectlve Representatlon.' Ethlcs. (1981(b)). Grofman, Eernard "The Theory of Connlttees and Electlons.' In Gordon Tullock (Ed.). Toward a Science oi Politics Elacksburg, VA: Public Choice Center, Virginlna Polytechnlc Instltute and State Unlverslty, 1981(c)' pp.11-17. Grofman, Eernard "Fair Apportlonment and the Banzhaf Index.' Amerlcan Mathematics tlonth'ly Vol. 88, No. I (1981(d) ), 1-5. Grofman, Eernard "For Single-Member Districts, Randm ls Not Equal.' In 8. Grofnan' A. L'lJphart, R. t'lcKay and H. Scarrow (Eds)' Representation and Redfstrlct'ing. Lexlngton, 1982(a), forthcomlng. Grofman, Bernard "Single-Member v. At-Large Electlons, Part I: Theoretical Issues.' Unpubllshed manuscrlpt, Schml of Setal Sclences, Unlverslty of Callfornla, Irvlne, 1982(b). s 5l50 Grofnan, Bernard 'Single-l.lember v. At-Large Electlons, Part II: A Revlew of 21 EnplrlcaI Studles, 1970-1980. Unpubllshed manuscrlpt, School of Soclal Sclences, Unlverslty of Callfornla, Irvine, 1982(c). Grofman, Bernard, Arend LiJphart, Robert l,lcKEy, and Howard Scarrow (Eds.), Representatlon and Redistricting Issues. Lexlngton: 1982' forthcoml ng. Srofman, Eernard and Howard Scarrow 'Iannuccl and lts Aftermath: The Applicatlon of the Banzhaf Index to llelghted Votlng in the State of l{ew York.' In Steven Erams et al. (Ed.), App'lled Gane Theory. Vlenna: Sprlnger-Verlag, 1980. Grofman, Eernard and Howard Scarrow 'The Riddle of Apportlonment--Eguallty of llhat?' Natlonal Clvlc Rorlev Vol. 70, ilo. 5 (l'lay 1981(a)' pp. 242'254. Grofman, Bernard and Horard Scarrow 'tlelghted Votlng: The Record ln New York County Government.r Legistatlve Stu Vol.5, t{o.2 (l'lay 1981(b), pp.287-304) Husen, Roger A. and Robert E. Crew 'The Pollcy Impact of Reapportlotuent.r Law and Soclety Revlew, Vol. 8 (Februuy 1973), pp. 69-93. Hardy, Rlchard J. and Kathryt N. Harmon 'The Impact of Reapportlonment on Pollcy Expendltures: A Quasl-Experimental Time-serles Analysls, 1957-1977.' Prepared for the Annual Meetlng of the l.lldrest Politlcal Sclence Assoclatlon' April 1979. H_oag, Clarence G. and George H. Hallett Jr. Proportional Repre:sntatlon. New York: l{acmlllan, 1925' (Reprlnted New York: l,lacmlllan, 1969). Jewell, Malcolm "Conmentary on tThe Court, The People' and '0ne Manr One Vote." In llelson Polsby (Ed.), Reapportlonnent ln the 1970's. Eerkeley: Unirersity of Callfornla Presst 1971, pp. 46-52. Jerell, I'lal colm *Ccmments: The Consequences of Slngle- and llultl-l'lember Dlstrlctlng." In B. Grofman, A. LiJphart, R. !'tcKay and H. Scarrou (Eds.). Representation and Redistrlctlng Iss , Lexlngton Books' (1982, forthcoming). Kendall, l,l. G. and A. Stuart *The Law of Cublc Proportlons ln Electlon Results.' Erltlsh Journal of Sociology, Vol. I (1950), 1A ff. Klaln, Haurlce 'A New Look at the Constltuencles: A Recount and a Reapprals!1.' lmerlcan Polltlca'l Sclence Revler (1955)' pp. 1105-1119. 52 Xdkllnskl, James 'Cumulatlve and Plurallty Votlng: .An Analysis of Illlnolst Unique E'lectoral System.' llestern Polltlcal Quarter'ly (1972), 9p, 726-746. Lucas, l{llllan F. . 'ileasurlng Power ln llelghted Votlng Systems.i Case Studies ln Applled l,lathematics. I'lathematics Assoclatlon of Amerlca, Module ln Applled }lathematlcs, 1976. (Origlna'lly publlshed as Technical Report W, Department of 0peratlons Research, College of Englneerlng, Cornell Unlrcrslty, Ithaca, l{ew York, September 1974). llacl,lanus, Susan A. 'Clty Corncll Electlon Procedures and I'tinorlty Representatlon: Are They Related?' Soclal Sclence Quarterly, Vol. 59, llo. I (June 1978), pp. 153-161. llr5fiar, Davld R. 'Congresslonal Representatlon: Theory and Practlce ln Drawlng the Olstricts.' In Nelson Polsby (Ed.), Reapportloment ln the 1970s. Berkeley: Unlrcrslty of Callfornla Press, 1971. HcKay, Robert B. Reapportionnent: The Law and Polltics of Equal Representatlon. ilfl t*- tlcKay, Robert B. 'Reapportiorment: Success Story of thel{arren Court.r illcflgan lgg Revian, Vol. 67 (1958), pg. 223-36 llusgrove, Phlllp The General Theory of Gerrjrmander{ng. Beverly Hllls, Callfornla: Sage Publlcrtlom, L977. 53 l{agel, Stuart xConputers and the Lav and Polltlcs of Redlstrlctlng.' !9]lg,f, Vol. 5 (1e72). llleml, Rlchard and John Deegan, Jr. *Ccmpetitlon, Responslveness and the Srlng Ratlo.r Atnedcq4 Politlcal Sclence Revlew, VoI. 72, t{0. 4 (Oecenber 1978), pp. 1304- 1323. llote: 'Proportional Representation 8y Race: The Constltutlonality of Benlgn Raclal Redlstrlctlng,' l,llchlgan Lar Revleu, Vol. 74 (1976), pp. 820-841. 0rRourke, Timothy The Impact of Reapportionment. l{ew Jersey: Transactlon 8ooks, 19&), ch. 1. Polsby, Nelson t{. (Ed.) Reapportlorment ln the 1970s. Eerkeley: Unlverslty of Callfornla Press, 1971. Rae, Dougl as The Political Consequences of Electoral Lavs. Ner Haven: YaIe Unlverslty Press, 1971. Ranney, Austin Curlng the l.lischlef of Faction: Party Refoym ln Anerlca. Berieley: Unlversity of California Prcss. Saffel, David rThe Pollcy Consequences of Reapportiorment.' In 8. Grofman, A. LiJphart, R. tlcKay and H. Scarrm (Eds)., Representatlon and .\ Redlstrlctlng Issues. Lexlngton: 198?, forthconlng. 54 55 Scarrm, Howard rCorrrents: The Impact of Reapportlorunent on Party Representation ln the State of t{erl York.' In B. Grofman, a LlJphart, R. l.lcKay and H. Scarrow (Eds.), Representatlon and Redlstrlcting Issues, Lexlngton Books, 1982, forthcomlng. (Reprlnted fron @, ' speclal lssue, l,larch 1981.) Scarror, Howard rThe Partlsan Consequences of Reapportlonent: tlhat l'le Can Learn frqn Ner York.' In B. Grofman, A. LlJphart, R. l-lcKay and H. Scarrow (Eds.), Representatlon and Redlstrictlng Issues. Lexlngton: 1982, Tufte, Edward R. 'The Relatlonshlp Between Seats and American Political Sclence Revlew, Votes ln Two-Party Systems.' Vol. 67 (1973) pp. 540-547. forthcoml ng. Slckels, R. J. 'Oragons, Bacon Reapportl orment. and Oumbbells: lrlho's Lar Journal, Vol. 75, I 300-1308. Sllva, Ruth C. 'Ccmpared Values of the Slngle and ilultl-l,lember Leglslatlve Dlstrict.' ttestern Politlcal Quarterly, Vol. 17 (September 1964), pp.504-516. Stlll, Jonathan. 'Polltlcal Equallty and Electlon Systems.r E!!lg, VoI. 91 (Aprll 1981). Tr{be, Lanrence Arnerlcan Constltutlonal Lan. itlnneola, llry York: Foundatlon Press, 1978. U. S. Conmlss'lon on Civil Rl ghts The Voting Rlghts Act: Ten Years After. U.S. Govt. hlntlng 0fflce' I 975. Usl aner, Erl c l''1. and Ronald E. l.leber "Reapportionment, Gerrymandering, and Change ln the Partisan Balance of Power in the Anerican States.' Paper presented at the Annual Ygq[inS of the lrnerlcan Polltlcal Sclence Assoclatlon. September llelchi'S0san and Albert K. Karnig. "Representatlon of Blacks on Big City School Eoards.' Soclal Science Quarterly, Vol. 59 (1978), pp. 152-171. tteltilTavlii-t. 'Af f i rmatl ve Gerrymanderl ng Conpounds Dlstrl ctl ng Probl ens.? &!!9!{ Civic Review (January 1978), pp. 10-17. llells, David I. nRedistrlctlng ln New York State: It's a Questlon of Sllclng the Salami.' Empire (October/November 1978), pp. 9-13. tlel'ls, Davld .Testlmony at Hearings before the Csnnlttee on Goverrmental Affalrs of the U.S. Senate on S.596, l{lnety-Stxth Congress' Flrst Sesslon.' U.S. Goverrment Prlntlng 0fflce' 1979. Strl ps, ' Yale Afrald of (July 1966), pp. 56 Illdgcn, Jolm f. rnd Rlchard L. Engstro l9&), pp. 123-435. Iolloct, lndrer J. (cd.) tcrpportlomcltil!-!41tsllglgg. 0olurr! lrtlonrl Gonfcrncc of Strtr tqlrlrtrm3. Jurt' 1080. 'r.1 ,' !. F F P IF rr liS ic i E E lS :l lr: :li != e -- l , aa a- l-A , : li a- -o ln Y , - l€ oo r r ti -l lo -- - - - I -- 6- a- t - ii r '-8 3- ' r . li ! i'E lL . a- i b .r € -la .li :r 1 li -5 a l- C O 16 da l- si li -l l- ;3 -1 3 tli ilg l! t- 3' riE 8E {3 oo a, !c a' 13 l- ac t6 I- lr :i- o 33 '5 -'5 1r = a- t ac < : -: d -e 1a ' -5 0a 6< ,t- -. Z o a3 r. '.B eP rF E ,e g: :! ':i E E i3 r *; i l :! iE s ;:i E :i lg : E -s ;E tE :E : i ii; ;;E = ;E qe ; ::= i:3 Iq : !s 9. :li s: le , -3 9? o- :" i! ?e a' o" !" I= ' -6 _- g tr ._ 3 ;_ - 3; -- "e 6. 3 :F g 'ti :;3 l.l ! i id 5; ,A r P Q n -< = -E = n -: i= ;i- if n -0 6 -o - l-P ;i- -; | - I o -- i- hi ; oo -l - ii; H c: ' { l= E :: i:; ie i a_ si :: i I : aI l'a i € it !i? .3 ri I:i = E i E i li ;3 8 :F - ;: !i3 -; 3 s! ? 5E 5 s5 5 ;a a_ cs : : -3 .E E i i.; li H ..- E b - a = T 'E ? ,- -a ai t aa oB : t. r ,i E iE l1 ie ;5 ig lt a1 t rs l: le ;E i; r; g* ! a' :r : :3 Ie , 53 : E ' gi : E E IE E iX : i il, ' tr -g D -. :B : 3E t5 3 3 a= = 2= . *L j" 7 aa < ci t it€ ni i:r ? -= i .= E = ' t 6E t; t ai i 3a B :i e a- . a E ' 3 aa ? I 3 a ii? ?; ::g lrl E tq ; ' - tlr e ; i2 c: E i' 6' .ii . 1 :3 ?; B I : :3 -4 -- r = ?t 1 : 3: E -' ? s a :r g 'i f,B - - - = - io ill i!: ;;i ::i q ^- -. -! ;:E :a -^ qi i!' :;; ;ii iiP gi S t:i il- :r :E B r, rj- - - ,= - o t I e i .9 -? q -3 . -- r ! E ; i 7l -. ;; - iii i;i iii i:E iil 'il s ;1 r i 1; . ., e .2 = .- ' -- l i e 'g s2 is !;l ii; ; ii ! iir i 2 it E l= E r ^- -? ; '2 ; ? = a= , ';, 1= - :- ' t.! : i:r '- , ; ';E . i.i ?a z E ? ai a; ::B c 3 5; - 9. '? si *i = zi r i :r ; ;i- . c : gc .i /- .o - e ai .1 1 -= 3e l i ? i{ ld :- = i.3 _ q i Ir ?: ; c E .: la i:i F : 3 E j;a ;! E - i:: E ? i e -1 5 1 A . - .L ? : ; A ilr s 't I ; ta - ;1 9 ? ; 1E u - , t tla zl et 3; = .3 Z = -7 ?t q i* i I i 1- . I- 5 - - - i6 i ? a - ;ta : ; q ii; E i i -; c- 3 € 3 21 i, ig ',e tc : o 3 iii - ; i,. a si i P : ?- lrt = ; E .t8 = L Z -= -- s- - r] 'll -1 1- Lr i-: = - ..- -- : .- -= -. .'- -: -. -'- j'- -- :J :- ::: .'l ;.- -': -" : ', -'i - ..- { .' . .- '-. 1 .e ' . :1 ., .. ' .: 'l- : :, -: . )